In our last chapter we
began considering objections to one very fundamental principle, which is
presupposed by the theory stated in the first two chapters—a principle
which may be summed up in the two propositions (1) that the question whether an
action is right or wrong always depends upon its total
consequences, and (2) that if it is once right to prefer one set of
total consequences, A, to another set,
B, it must always be right to prefer any set precisely
similar to A to any set precisely similar to
B. The objections to this principle, which we considered in
the last chapter, rested on certain views with
regard to the meaning of the words right
and good.
But there remain several other quite independent objections, which may be urged
against it even if we reject those views. That is to say, there are objections
which may and would be urged against it by many people who accept both of the
two propositions which I was trying to establish in the last chapter, namely (1) that to call an action
right
or wrong
is not the same thing as to say
that any being whatever has towards it any mental attitude whatever; and (2)
that if any given whole is once intrinsically good or bad, any whole precisely
similar to it must always be intrinsically good or bad in precisely the same
degree. And in the present chapter I wish briefly to consider what seem to me to
be the most important of these remaining objections.(Ch. 5 ¶ 1)
All of them are directed against the view that right and wrong do always depend upon an action’s actual consequences or results. This may be denied for several different reasons; and I shall try to state fairly the chief among these reasons, and to point out why they do not seem to be conclusive.(Ch. 5 ¶ 2)
In the first place, it may be said that, by laying down the
principle that right and wrong depend upon consequences, we are doing away with
the distinction between what is a duty and what is merely
expedient; and between what is wrong
and what is merely inexpedient. People certainly do
commonly make a distinction between duty and expediency. And it may be said that
the very meaning of calling an action expedient
is to say that it
will produce the best consequences possible under the circumstances. If,
therefore, we also say that an action is a duty, whenever
and only when it produces the best possible consequences, it may seem that
nothing is left to distinguish duty from expediency.(Ch. 5 ¶ 3)
Now, as against this objection, it is important to point
out, first of all, that, even if we admit that to call an action expedient is
the same thing as to say that it produces the best possible consequences, our
principle still does not compel us to hold that to call an action expedient is
the same thing as to call it a duty. All that it does
compel us to hold is that whatever is expedient is always
also a duty, and that whatever is a duty is always
also expedient. That is to say, it
does maintain that duty and expediency
coincide; but it does not maintain
that the meaning of the two words is the same. It is, indeed, quite plain, I
think, that the meaning of the two words is not the same;
for, if it were, then it would be a mere tautology to say that it is always our
duty to do what will have the best possible consequences. Our theory does not,
therefore, do away with the distinction between the meaning
of the words duty
and expediency
; it only
maintains that both will always apply to the same actions.(Ch. 5 ¶ 4)
But, no doubt, what is meant by many who urge this
objection is to deny this. What they mean to say is not merely that to call an
action expedient is a different thing from calling it a duty, but also that
sometimes what is expedient is wrong,
and what is a duty is inexpedient. This is a view which is
undoubtedly often held; people often speak as if there often were an actual
conflict between duty and expediency. But many of the cases in which it would be
commonly held that there is such a conflict may, I think, be explained by
supposing that when we call an action expedient
we do not always
mean quite strictly that its total consequences, taking
absolutely everything into account, are the best possible.
It is by no means clear that we do always mean this. We may, perhaps, sometimes
mean merely that the action is expedient for some particular purpose; and
sometimes that it is expedient in the interests of the agent, though not so on
the whole. But if we only mean this, our theory, of course, does
not compel us to maintain that the expedient
is always a duty, and duty always an expedient. It only
compels us to maintain this, if expedient
be understood in the
strictest and fullest sense, as meaning that, when absolutely
all the consequences are taken into account, they will be found to be
the best possible. And if this be clearly understood, then most people, I think,
will be reluctant to admit that it can ever be really inexpedient to do our
duty, or that what is really and truly expedient, in this strict sense, can ever
be wrong.(Ch. 5 ¶ 5)
But, no doubt, some people may still maintain that it is or may be sometimes our duty to do actions which will not have the best possible consequences, and sometimes also positively wrong, to do actions which will. And the chief reason why this is held is, I think, the following.(Ch. 5 ¶ 6)
It is, in fact, very commonly held indeed that there are certain specific kinds of action which are absolutely always right, and others which are absolutely always wrong. Different people will, indeed, take different views as to exactly what kinds of action have this character. A rule which will be offered by one set of persons as a rule to which there is absolutely no exception will be rejected by others, as obviously admitting of exceptions; but these will generally, in their turn, maintain that some other rule, which they can mention, really has no exceptions. Thus there are enormous numbers of people who would agree that some rule or other (and generally more than one) ought absolutely always to be obeyed; although probably there is not one single rule which all the persons who maintain this would agree upon. Thus, for instance, some people might maintain that murder (defined in some particular way) is an act which ought absolutely never to be committed; or that to act justly is a rule which ought absolutely always to be obeyed; and similarly it might be suggested with regard to many other kinds of actions, that they are actions, which it is either always our duty, or always wrong to do.(Ch. 5 ¶ 7)
But once we assert with regard to any rule of this kind
that it is absolutely always our duty to obey it, it is
easy and natural to take one further step and to say that it
would always be our duty to obey it,
whatever the consequences might be. Of course, this further
step does not necessarily and logically follow from the mere position that there
are some kinds of action which ought, in fact, absolutely
always to be done or avoided. For it is just possible that there are some kinds
which do, as a matter of fact, absolutely always produce the best possible
consequences, and other kinds which absolutely never do so. And there is a
strong tendency among persons who hold the first position to hold that, as a
matter of fact, this is the case: that right actions always do, as a matter of
fact, produce the best possible results, and wrong actions never. Thus even
those who would assent to the maxim that Justice should always be done,
though the heavens should falls,
will generally be disposed to believe
that justice never will, in fact, cause the heavens to fall, but will rather be
always the best means of upholding them. And similarly those who say that
you should never do evil that good may come,
though their maxim
seems to imply that good may sometimes come from doing
wrong, would yet be very loth to admit that, by doing wrong, you ever would
really produce better consequences on the
whole than if you had acted rightly instead. Or again, those who say
that the end will never justify the means,
though they certainly
imply that certain ways of acting would be always wrong,
whatever advantages might be secured by them, yet, I think,
would be inclined to deny that the advantages to be obtained by acting wrongly
ever do really outweigh those to be obtained by acting
rightly, if we take into account absolutely all the
consequences of each course.(Ch. 5 ¶ 8)
Those, therefore, who hold that certain specific ways of
acting are absolutely always right, and others absolutely always wrong, do, I
think, generally hold that the former do also, as a matter of fact, absolutely
always produce the best results, and the latter never. But, for the reasons given at the beginning of Chapter
III, it is, I think, very unlikely
that this belief can be justified. The total results of an action always depend,
not merely on the specific nature of the action, but on the circumstances in
which it is done; and the circumstances vary so greatly that it is, in most
cases, extremely unlikely that any particular kind of action will
absolutely always, in absolutely all circumstances, either
produce or fail to produce the best possible results. For this reason, if we do
take the view that right and wrong depend upon consequences, we must, I think,
be prepared to doubt whether any particular kind of action whatever is
absolutely always right or absolutely always wrong. For instance, however we
define murder,
it is unlikely that absolutely
no case will ever occur in which it would be right to
commit a murder; and, however we define justice,
it is unlikely
that no case will ever occur in which it would be right to
do an injustice. No doubt it may be possible to define actions of which it is
true that, in an immense majority of cases, it is right or
wrong to perform them; and perhaps some rules of this kind
might be found to which there are really no exceptions. But
in the case of most of the ordinary moral rules, it seems extremely unlikely
that obedience to them will absolutely always produce the
best possible results. And most persons who realise this would, I think, be
disposed to give up the view that they ought absolutely
always to be obeyed. They would be content to accept them
as general rules, to which there are very few exceptions,
without pretending that they are absolutely universal.(Ch. 5 ¶ 9)
But, no doubt, there may be some persons who will hold, in
the case of some particular rule or set of rules, that even if obedience to it
does in some cases not produce the best possible
consequences, yet we ought even in these cases to obey it. It may seem to them
that they really do know certain rules, which ought absolutely
always to be obeyed, whatever the consequences
may be, and even, therefore, if the total consequences are not the best
possible. They may, for instance, take quite seriously the assertion that
justice ought to be done, even though the heavens should fall, as meaning that,
however bad the consequences of doing an act of justice
might in some circumstances be, yet it always would be our duty to do it. And
such a view does necessarily contradict our principle; since, whether it be true
or not that an act of injustice ever actually could in this world produce the
best possible consequences, it is certainly possible to
conceive circumstances in which it would do so. I doubt
whether those who believe in the absolute universality of certain moral rules do
generally thus distinguish quite clearly between the question whether
disobedience to the rule ever could produce the best
possible consequences, and the question whether, if it did,
then disobedience would be wrong. They would generally be disposed to argue that
it never really could. But some persons might perhaps hold
that, even if it did, yet disobedience would be wrong. And if this view be quite
clearly held, there is, so far as I can see, absolutely no way of refuting it
except by appealing to the self-evidence of the principle that if we
knew that the effect of a given action really would be to
make the world, as a whole, worse than it would have been
if we had acted differently, it certainly would be wrong for us to do that
action. Those who say that certain rules ought absolutely
always to be obeyed, whatever the consequences
may be, are logically bound to deny this; for by saying
whatever the consequences may be,
they do
imply even if the world as a whole were the worse
because of our action.
It seems to me to be self-evident that knowingly
to do an action which would make the world, on the whole, really and truly
worse than if we had acted differently, must always be
wrong. And if this be admitted, then it absolutely disposes of the view that
there are any kinds of actions whatever, which it would
always be our duty to do or to avoid, whatever the
consequences might be.(Ch. 5 ¶ 10)
For this reason it seems to me we must reject this particular objection to the view that right and wrong always depend upon consequences; namely, the objection that there are certain kinds of action which ought absolutely always and quite unconditionally to be done or avoided. But there still remain two other objections, which are so commonly held, that it is worth while to consider them.(Ch. 5 ¶ 11)
The first is the objection that righ wrong depend neither upon the nature of the action, nor upon its consequences, but partly, or even entirely, upon the motive or motives from which it is done. By the view that it depends partly upon the motives, I mean the view that no action can be really right, unless it be done from some one motive or some one of a set of motives, which are supposed to be good; but that the being done from such a motive is not sufficient, by itself, to make an action right: that the action, if it is to be right, must always also either produce the best possible consequences, or be distinguished by some other characteristic. And this view, therefore, will not necessarily contradict our principle so far as it asserts that no action can be right, unless it produces the best possible consequences: it only contradicts that part of it which asserts that every action which does produce them is right. But the view has sometimes been held, I think, that right and wrong depend entirely upon motives: that is to say, that not only is no action right, unless it be done from a good motive, but also that any action which is done from some one motive or some one of a set of motives is always right, whatever the consequences may be and whatever it may be like in other respects. And this view, of course, will contradict both parts of our principle; since it not only implies that an action, which produces the best possible consequences may be wrong, but also that an action may be right, in spite of failing to produce them.(Ch. 5 ¶ 12)
In favour of both these views it may be urged that in our
moral judgments we actually do, and ought to, take account of motives; and
indeed that it marks a great advance in morality when men do begin to attach
importance to motives and are not guided exclusively in their praise or blame,
by the external
nature of the act done or by its consequences.
And all this may be fully admitted. It is quite certain that when a man does an
action which has bad consequences from a good motive, we do tend to judge him
differently from a man who does a similar action from a bad one; and also that
when a man does an action which has good consequences from a bad motive, we may
nevertheless think badly of him for it. And it may be admitted that, in some
cases at least, it is right and proper that a man’s motives should thus
influence our judgment. But the question is: What sort of
moral judgment is it right and proper that they should influence? Should it
influence our view as to whether the action in question is right or wrong? It
seems very doubtful whether, as a rule, it actually does affect our judgment on
this particular point, for we are quite accustomed to judge that a man sometimes
acts wrongly from the best of motives; and though we should
admit that the good motive forms some excuse, and that the whole state of things
is better than if he had done the same thing from a bad motive, it yet does not
lead us to deny that the action is wrong. There is,
therefore, reason to think that the kind of moral judgments which a
consideration of motives actually does affect do not
consist of judgments as to whether the action done from the motive is
right or wrong; but are moral
judgments of some different kind; and there is still more
reason to think that it is only judgments of some different kind which
ought to be influenced by it.(Ch. 5 ¶ 13)
The fact is that judgments as to the rightness and wrongness of actions are by no means the only kind of moral judgments which we make; and it is, I think, solely because some of these other judgments are confused with judgments of right and wrong that the latter are ever held to depend upon the motive. There are three other kinds of judgments which are chiefly concerned in this case. In the first place it may be held that some motives are intrinsically good and others intrinsically bad; and though this is a view which is inconsistent with the theory of our first two chapters, it is not a view which we are at present concerned to dispute: for it is not at all inconsistent with the principle which we are at present considering—namely, that right and wrong always depend solely upon consequences. If we held this view, we might still hold that a man may act wrongly from a good motive, and rightly from a bad one, and that the motive would make no difference whatever to the rightness or wrongness of the action. What it would make a difference to is the goodness or badness of the whole state of affairs: for, if we suppose the same action to be done in one case from a good motive and in the other from a bad one, then, so far as the consequences of the action are concerned, the goodness of the whole state of things will be the same, while the presence of the good motive will mean the presence of an additional good in the one case which is absent in the other. For this reason alone, therefore, we might justify the view that motives are relevant to some kinds of moral judgments, though not to judgments of right and wrong.(Ch. 5 ¶ 14)
And there is yet another reason for this view, and this a reason which may be consistently held even by those who hold the theory of our first two chapters. It may be held, namely, that good motives have a general tendency to produce right conduct, though they do not always do so, and bad motives to produce wrong conduct; and this would be another reason which would justify us in regarding right actions done from a good motive differently from right actions done from a bad one. For though, in the case supposed, the bad motive would not actually have led to wrong action, yet, if it is true that motives of that kind do generally lead to wrong action, we should be right in passing this judgment upon it; and judgments to the effect that a motive is of a kind which generally leads to wrong action are undoubtedly moral judgments of a sort, and an important sort, though they do not prove that every action done from such a motive is wrong.(Ch. 5 ¶ 15)
And finally motives seem also to be relevant to a third kind of moral judgment of great importance—namely, judgments as to whether, and in what degree, the agent deserves moral praise or blame for acting as he did. This question as to what is deserving of moral praise or blame is, I think, often confused with the question as to what is right or wrong. It is very natural, at first sight, to assume that to call an action morally praiseworthy is the same thing as to say that it is right, and to call it morally blameworthy the same thing as to say that it is wrong. But yet a very little reflection suffices to show that the two things are certainly distinct. When we say that an action deserves praise or blame, we imply that it is right to praise or blame it; that is to say, we are making a judgment not about the rightness of the original action, but about the rightness of the further action which we should take, if we praised or blamed it. And these two judgments are certainly not identical; nor is there any reason to think that what is right always also deserves to be praised, and what is wrong always also deserves to be blamed. Even, therefore, if the motive is relevant to the question whether an action deserves praise or blame, it by no means follows that it is also relevant to the question whether it is right or wrong. And there is some reason to think that the motive is relevant to judgments of the former kind: that we really ought sometimes to praise an action done from a bad motive less than if it had been done from a good one, and to blame an action done from a good motive less than if it had been done from a bad one. For one of the considerations upon which the question whether it is right to blame an action depends, is that our blame may tend to prevent the agent from doing similar wrong actions in future; and obviously, if the agent only acted wrongly from a motive which is not likely to lead him wrong in the future, there is less need to try to deter him by blame than if he had acted from a motive which was likely to lead him to act wrongly again. This is, I think, a very real reason why we sometimes ought to blame a man less when he does wrong from a good motive. But I do not mean to say that the question whether a man deserves moral praise or blame, or the degree to which he deserves it, depends entirely or always upon his motive. I think it certainly does not. My point is only that this question does sometimes depend on the motive in some degree; whereas the question whether his action was right or wrong never depends on it at all.(Ch. 5 ¶ 16)
There are, therefore, at least three different kinds of moral judgments, in making which it is at least plausible to hold that we ought to take account of motives; and if all these judgments are carefully distinguished from that particular kind which is solely concerned with the question whether an action is right or wrong, there ceases, I think, to be any reason to suppose that this last question ever depends upon the motive at all. At all events the mere fact that motives are and ought to be taken account of in some moral judgments does not constitute such a reason. And hence this fact cannot be urged as an objection to the view that right and wrong depend solely on consequences.(Ch. 5 ¶ 17)
But there remains one last objection to this view, which is, I am inclined to think, the most serious of all. This is an objection which will be urged by people who strongly maintain that right and wrong do not depend either upon the nature of the action or upon its motive, and who will even go so far as to admit as self-evident the hypothetical proposition that if any being absolutely knew that one action would have better total consequences than another, then it would always be his duty to choose the former rather than the latter. But what such people would point out is that this hypothetical case is hardly ever, if ever, realised among us men. We hardly ever, if ever, know for certain which among the courses open to us will produce the best consequences. Some accident, which we could not possibly have forseen, may always falsify the most careful calculations, and make an action, which we had every reason to think would have the best results, actually have worse ones than some alternative would have had. Suppose, then, that a man has taken all possible care to assure himself that a given course will be the best, and has adopted it for that reason, but that owing to some subsequent event, which he could not possibly have forseen, it turns out not to be the best: are we for that reason to say that his action was wrong? It may seem outrageous to say so; and yet this is what we must say, if we are to hold that right and wrong depend upon the actual consequences. Or suppose that a man has deliberately chosen a course, which he has every reason to suppose will not produce the best consequences, but that some unforseen accident defeats his purpose and makes it actually turn out to be the best: are we to say that such a man, because of this unforseen accident, has acted rightly? This also may seem an outrageous thing to say; and yet we must say it, if we are to hold that right and wrong depend upon the actual consequences. For these reasons many people are strongly inclined to hold that they do not depend upon the actual consequences, but only upon those which were antecedently probable, or which the agent had reason to expect, or which it was possible for him to forsee. They are inclined to say that an action is always right, whatever its actual consequences may be, provided the agent had reason to expect that they would be the best possible; and always wrong, if he had reason to expect that they would not.(Ch. 5 ¶ 18)
This, I think, is the most serious objection to the view that right and wrong depend upon the actual consequences. But yet I am inclined to think that even this objection can be got over by reference to the distinction between what is right or wrong, on the one hand, and what is morally praiseworthy or blameworthy on the other. What we should naturally say of a man whose action turns out badly owing to some unforseen accident when he had every reason to expect that it would turn out well, is not that his action was right, but rather that he is not to blame. And it may be fully admitted that in such a case he really ought not to be blamed; since blame cannot possibly serve any good purpose, and would be likely to do harm. But, even if we admit that he was not to blame, is that any reason for asserting also that he acted rightly? I cannot see that it is; and therefore I am inclined to think that in all such cases the man really did act wrongly, although he is not to blame, and although, perhaps, he even deserves praise for acting as he did.(Ch. 5 ¶ 19)
But the same difficulty may be put in another form, in which there may seem an even stronger case against the view that right and wrong depend on the actual consequences. Instead of considering what judgment we ought to pass on an action after it has been done, and when many of its results are already known, let us consider what judgment we ought to pass on it beforehand, and when the question is which among several courses still open to a man he ought to choose. It is admitted that he cannot know for certain beforehand which of them will actually have the best results; but let us suppose that he has every reason to think that one of them will produce decidedly better results than any of the others—that all probability is in favour of this view. Can we not say, in such a case, that he absolutely ought to choose that one? that he will be acting very wrongly if he chooses any other? We certainly should actually say so; and many people may be inclined to think that we should be right in saying so, no matter what the results may subsequently prove to be. There does seem to be a certain paradox in maintaining the opposite: in maintaining that, in such a case, it can possibly be true that he ought to choose a course, which he has every reason to think will not be the best. But yet I am inclined to think that even this difficulty is not fatal to our view. It may be admitted that we should say, and should be justified in saying, that he absolutely ought to choose the course, which he has reason to think will be the best. But we may be justified in saying many things, which we do not know to be true, and which in fact are not so, provided that there is a strong probability that they are. And so in this case I do not see why we should not hold, that though we should be justified in saying that he ought to choose one course, yet it may not be really true that he ought. What certainly will be true is that he will deserve the strongest moral blame if he does not choose the course in question, even though it may be wrong. And we are thus committed to the paradox that a man may really deserve the strongest moral condemnation for choosing an action, which actually is right. But I do not see why we should not accept this paradox.(Ch. 5 ¶ 20)
I conclude, then, that there is no conclusive reason against the view that our theory is right, so far as it maintains that the question whether an action is right or wrong always depends on its actual consequences. There seems no sufficient reason for holding either that it depends on the intrinsic nature of the action, or that it depends upon the motive, or even that it depends on the probable consequences.(Ch. 5 ¶ 21)
Ethics was written by G. E. Moore, and published in in 1912. It is now available in the Public Domain.