Chapter V: Ethics in Relation to Conduct.
§ 106.
In order, however, justly to consider the claims of virtue to intrinsic value, it is necessary to distinguish several very different mental states, all of which fall under the general definition that they are habitual dispositions to perform duties. We may thus distinguish three very different states, all of which are liable to be confused with one another, upon each of which different moral systems have laid great stress, and for each of which the claim has been made that it alone constitutes virtue, and, by implication, that it is the sole good. We may first of all distinguish between (a) that permanent characteristic of mind, which consists in the fact that the performance of duty has become in the strict sense a habit, like many of the operations performed in the putting on of clothes, and (b) that permanent characteristic, which consists in the fact that what may be called good motives habitually help to cause the performance of duties. And in the second division we may distinguish between the habitual tendency to be actuated by one motive, namely, the desire to do duty for duty’s sake, and all other motives, such as love, benevolence, etc. We thus get the three kinds of virtue, of which we are now to consider the intrinsic value. (§ 106 ¶ 1)
(a) There is no doubt that a man’s character may be such
that he habitually performs certain duties, without the thought ever occurring
to him, when he wills them, either that they are duties or that any good will
result from them. Of such a man we cannot and do not refuse to say that he
possesses the virtue consisting in the disposition to perform those duties. I,
for instance, am honest in the sense that I habitually abstain from any of the
actions legally qualified as thieving, even where some other persons would be
strongly tempted to commit them. It would be grossly contrary to common usage to
deny that, for this reason, I really have the virtue of honesty: it is quite
certain that I have an habitual disposition to perform a duty. And that as many
people as possible should have a like disposition is, no doubt, of great
utility: it is good as a means. Yet I may safely assert that neither my various
performances of this duty, nor my disposition to perform them, have the smallest
intrinsic value. It is because the majority of instances of virtue seem to be of
this nature, that we may venture to assert that virtues have, in general, no
intrinsic value whatsoever. And there seems to be good reason to think that the
more generally they are of this nature the more useful they are; since a great
economy of labour is effected when a useful action becomes habitual or
instinctive. But to maintain that a virtue which includes no more than this, is
good in itself is a gross absurdity. And of this gross absurdity, it may be
observed, the Ethics of Aristotle is guilty. For his definition of virtue does
not exclude a disposition to perform actions in this way, whereas his
descriptions of the particular virtues plainly include such actions:
that an action, in order to exhibit virtue, must be done τοῦ καλοῦ ἓνεκα is
a qualification which he allows often to drop out of sight. And, on the other
hand, he seems certainly to regard the exercise of all virtues as an
end in itself. His treatment of Ethics is indeed, in the most important points,
highly unsystematic and confused, owing to his attempt to base it on the
naturalistic fallacy; for strictly we should be obliged by his words to regard
θεωπία as the only thing good in itself, in
which case the goodness which he attributes to the practical virtues cannot be
intrinsic value; while on the other hand he does not seem to regard it merely as
utility, since he makes no attempt to shew that they are means to θεωπία. But there seems no doubt that on the whole he
regards the exercise of the practical virtues as a good of the same kind as
(i.e. having intrinsic
value), only in a less degree than, θεωπία; so that
he cannot avoid the charge that he recommends as having intrinsic value, such
instances of the exercise of virtue as we are at present
discussing—instances of a disposition to perform actions which, in the
modern phrase, have merely an external rightness.
That he is right in
applying the word virtue
to such a disposition cannot be doubted. But the
protest against the view that external rightness
is sufficient to
constitute either duty
or virtue
—a protest which is
commonly, and with some justice, attributed as a merit to Christian
morals—seems, in the main, to be a mistaken way of pointing out an
important truth: namely, that where there is only external rightness
there is certainly no intrinsic value. It is commonly assumed (though wrongly)
that to call a thing a virtue means that it has intrinsic value: and on this
assumption the view that virtue does not consist in a mere disposition to do
externally right actions does really constitute an advance in ethical truth
beyond the Ethics of Aristotle. The inference that, if virtue includes in its
meaning good in itself,
then Aristotle’s definition of virtue is
not adequate and expresses a false ethical judgment, is perfectly correct: only
the premise that virtue does include this in its meaning is mistaken. (§ 106 ¶ 2)