Chapter VI: The Ideal.
§ 134.
I have now completed such remarks as seemed most necessary to be
made concerning intrinsic values. It is obvious that for the proper answering of
this, the fundamental question of Ethics, there remains a field of investigation
as wide and as difficult, as was assigned to Practical Ethics in my last chapter. There
is as much to be said concerning what results are intrinsically good, and in
what degrees, as concerning what results it is possible for us to bring about:
both questions demand, and will repay, an equally patient enquiry. Many of the
judgments, which I have made in this chapter, will, no doubt, seem unduly
arbitrary: it must be confessed that some of the attributions of intrinsic
value, which have seemed to me to be true, do not display that symmetry and
system which is wont to be required of philosophers. But if this be urged as an
objection, I may respectfully point out that it is none. We have no title
whatever to assume that the truth on any subject-matter will display such
symmetry as we desire to see—or (to use the common vague phrase) that it
will possess any particular form of unity.
To search for unity
and
system,
at the expense of truth, is not, I take it, the proper business
of philosophy, however universally it may have been the practice of
philosophers. And that all truths about the Universe possess to one another all
the various relations, which may be meant by unity,
can only be
legitimately asserted, when we have carefully distinguished those various
relations and discovered what those truths are. In particular, we can have no
title to assert that ethical truths are unified
in any particular manner,
except in virtue of an enquiry conducted by the method which I have endeavoured
to follow and to illustrate. The study of Ethics would, no doubt, be far more
simple, and its results far more systematic,
if, for instance, pain were
an evil of exactly the same magnitude as pleasure is a good; but we have no
reason whatever to assume that the Universe is such that ethical truths must
display this kind of symmetry: no argument against my conclusion, that pleasure and pain do
not thus correspond, can have any weight whatever, failing a
careful examination of the instances which have led me to form it. Nevertheless
I am content that the results of this chapter should be taken rather as
illustrating the method which must be pursued in answering the fundamental
question of Ethics, and the principles which must be observed, than as giving
the correct answer to that question. That things intrinsically good or bad are
many and various; that most of them are organic unities,
in the peculiar and
definite sense to which I have confined the term; and that our only means of
deciding upon their intrinsic value and its degree, is by carefully
distinguishing exactly what the thing is, about which we ask the question, and
then looking to see whether it has or has not the unique predicate good
in any of its various degrees: these are the conclusions, upon the truth of
which I desire to insist. Similarly, in my last chapter,
with regard to the question What ought we to do?
I have endeavoured
rather to shew exactly
what is the meaning of the question, and what difficulties must consequently be faced in answering
it, than to prove that any particular answers are true. And that these two
questions, having precisely the nature which I have assigned to them, are
the questions which it is the object of Ethics to answer, may be
regarded as the main result of the preceding chapters. These are the questions
which ethical philosophers have always been mainly concerned to answer, although
they have not recognised what their question was—what predicate they were
asserting to attach to things. The practice of asking what things are virtues or
duties, without distinguishing what these terms mean; the practice of asking
what ought to be here and now, without distinguishing whether as means or
end—for its own sake or for that of its results; the search for one single
criterion of right and wrong, without the recognition that in order to
discover a criterion we must first know what things are right and
wrong; and the neglect of the principle of organic unities
—these
sources of error have hitherto been almost universally prevalent in Ethics. The
conscious endeavour to avoid them all, and to apply to all the ordinary objects
of ethical judgment these two questions and these only: Has it intrinsic value?
and Is it a means to the best possible?—this attempt, so far as I know, is
entirely new; and its results, when compared with those habitual to moral
philosophers, are certainly sufficiently surprising: that to Common Sense they
will not appear so strange, I venture to hope and believe. It is, I think, much
to be desired that the labour commonly devoted to answering such questions as
whether certain ends
are more or less comprehensive
or more or
less consistent
with one another—questions, which, even if a
precise meaning were given to them, are wholly irrelevant to the proof of any
ethical conclusion—should be diverted to the separate investigation of
these two clear problems. (§ 134 ¶ 1)