Chapter II: Naturalistic Ethics.
§ 29.
To argue that
a thing is good because it is natural,
or bad because
it is unnatural,
in these common senses of the term, is therefore
certainly fallacious; and yet such arguments are very frequently used. But they
do not commonly pretend to give a systematic theory of Ethics. Among attempts to
systematise an appeal to nature, that which is now most prevalent is to
be found in the application to ethical questions of the term
Evolution
—in the ethical doctrines which have been called
Evolutionistic.
These doctrines are those which maintain that the course
of evolution,
while it shews us the direction in which we are
developing, thereby and for that reason shews us the direction in which we
ought to develop. Writers, who maintain such a doctrine, are at present
very numerous and very popular; and I propose to take as my example the writer,
who is perhaps best known of them all—Mr Herbert
Spencer. Mr Spencer’s doctrine, it must be owned, does not offer the
clearest example of the naturalistic fallacy as used in support of
Evolutionistic Ethics. A clearer example might be found in Guyau,
a writer who has lately had considerable vogue in France, but who is not so well
known as Spencer. Guyau might almost be called a disciple of Spencer; he is
frankly evolutionistic, and frankly naturalistic; and I may mention that he does
not seem to think that he differs from Spencer by reason of his naturalism. The
point in which he has criticised Spencer concerns the question how far the ends
of pleasure
and of increased life
coincide as motives and means to
the attainment of the ideal: he does not seem to think that he differs from
Spencer in the fundamental principle that the ideal is Quantity of life,
measured in breadth as well as in length,
or, as Guyau says, Expansion and
intensity of life
; nor in the naturalistic reason which he gives for this
principle. And I am not sure that he does differ from Spencer in these points.
Spencer does, as I shall shew, use the naturalistic fallacy in details; but with
regard to his fundamental principles, the following doubts occur: Is he
fundamentally a Hedonist? And, if so, is he a naturalistic Hedonist? In that
case he would better have been treated in my next
chapter. Does he hold that a tendency to increase quantity of life is merely
a criterion of good conduct? Or does he hold that such increase of life
is marked out by nature as an end at which we ought to aim? (§ 29 ¶ 1)
I think his language in various places would give colour to all these hypotheses; though some of them are mutually inconsistent. I will try to discuss the main points. (§ 29 ¶ 2)
§ 29, n. 1: See Esquisse d'une Morale sans Obligation ni Sanction, par M. Guyau. 4me édition. Paris: F. Alcan, 1896. ↩