Chapter II: Naturalistic Ethics.
§ 34.
It remains only to
state clearly what is definitely fallacious in prevalent views as to the
relation of Evolution to Ethics—in those views with regard to which it
seems so uncertain how far Mr Spencer intends to
encourage them. I propose to confine the term Evolutionistic Ethics
to
the view that we need only to consider the tendency of evolution
in order
to discover the direction in which we ought to go. This view must be
carefully distinguished from certain others, which may be commonly confused with
it. (1) It might, for instance, be held that the direction in which living
things have hitherto developed is, as a matter of fact, the direction of
progress. It might be held that the more evolved
is, as a matter of fact,
also better. And in such a view no fallacy is involved. But, if it is to give us
any guidance as to how we ought to act in the future, it does involve a long and
painful investigation of the exact points in which the superiority of the more
evolved consists. We cannot assume that, because evolution is progress on
the whole, therefore every point in which the more evolved differs from the
less is a point in which it is better than the less. A simple consideration of
the course of evolution will therefore, on this view, by no means suffice to
inform us of the course we ought to pursue. We shall have to employ all the
resources of a strictly ethical discussion in order to arrive at a correct
valuation of the different results of evolution—to distinguish the more
valuable from the less valuable, and both from those which are no better than
their causes, or perhaps even worse. In fact it is difficult to see how, on this
view—if all that be meant is that evolution has on the whole been
a progress—the theory of evolution can give any assistance to Ethics at
all. The judgment that evolution has been a progress is itself an independent
ethical judgment; and even if we take it to be more certain and obvious than any
of the detailed judgments upon which it must logically depend for confirmation,
we certainly cannot use it as a datum from which to infer details. It is, at all
events, certain that, if this had been the only relation held to exist
between Evolution and Ethics, no such importance would have been attached to the
bearing of Evolution on Ethics as we actually find claimed for it. (2) The view,
which, as I have said, seems to be Mr
Spencer’s main view, may also be held without fallacy. It may be held that
the more evolved, though not itself the better, is a criterion, because
a concomitant, of the better. But this view also obviously involves an
exhaustive preliminary discussion of the fundamental ethical question what,
after all, is better. That Mr Spencer entirely
dispenses with such a discussion in support of his contention that pleasure is
the sole good, I have pointed out; and that, if we attempt such a discussion, we
shall arrive at no such simple result, I shall presently try to shew. If however
the good is not simple, it is by no means likely that we shall be able to
discover Evolution to be a criterion of it. We shall have to establish a
relation between two highly complicated sets of data; and, moreover, if we had
once settled what were goods, and what their comparative values, it is extremely
unlikely that we should need to call in the aid of Evolution as a criterion of
how to get the most. It is plain, then, again, that if this were the only
relation imagined to exist between Evolution and Ethics, it could hardly have
been thought to justify the assignment of any importance in Ethics to the theory
of Evolution. Finally, (3) it may be held that, though Evolution gives us no
help in discovering what results of our efforts will be best, it does give some
help in discovering what it is possible to attain and what are the
means to its attainment. That the theory really may be of service to Ethics in
this way cannot be denied. But it is certainly not common to find this humble,
ancillary bearing clearly and exclusively assigned to it. In the mere fact,
then, that these non-fallacious views of the relation of Evolution to Ethics
would give so very little importance to that relation, we have evidence that
what is typical in the coupling of the two names is the fallacious view to which
I propose to restrict the name Evolutionistic Ethics.
This is the view
that we ought to move in the direction of evolution simply because it
is the direction of evolution. That the forces of Nature are working on that
side is taken as a presumption that it is the right side. That such a view,
apart from metaphysical presuppositions, with which I shall presently deal, is
simply fallacious, I have tried to shew. It can only rest on a confused belief
that somehow the good simply means the side on which Nature is working.
And it thus involves another confused belief which is very marked in Mr Spencer’s whole treatment of Evolution. For,
after all, is Evolution the side on which Nature is working? In the sense, which
Mr Spencer gives to the term, and in any sense in
which it can be regarded as a fact that the more evolved is higher, Evolution
denotes only a temporary historical process. That things will
permanently continue to evolve in the future, or that they have always evolved
in the past, we have not the smallest reason to believe. For Evolution does not,
in this sense, denote a natural law, like the law of gravity.
Darwin’s theory of natural selection does indeed state a natural law: it
states that, given certain conditions, certain results will always happen. But
Evolution, as Mr Spencer understands it and as it is
commonly understood, denotes something very different. It denotes only a process
which has actually occurred at a given time, because the conditions at the
beginning of that time happened to be of a certain nature. That such conditions
will always be given, or have always been given, cannot be assumed; and it is
only the process which, according to natural law, must follow from
these conditions and no others, that appears to be also on the whole a
progress. Precisely the same natural laws—Darwin’s, for
instance—would under other conditions render inevitable not
Evolution—not a development from lower to higher—but the converse
process, which has been called Involution. Yet Mr
Spencer constantly speaks of the process which is exemplified by the development
of man as if it had all the augustness of a universal Law of Nature: whereas we
have no reason to believe it other than a temporary accident, requiring not only
certain universal natural laws, but also the existence of a certain state of
things at a certain time. The only laws concerned in the matter are
certainly such as, under other circumstances, would allow us to infer, not the
development, but the extinction of man. And that circumstances will always be
favourable to further development, that Nature will always work on the side of
Evolution, we have no reason whatever to believe. Thus the idea that Evolution
throws important light on Ethics seems to be due to a double confusion. Our
respect for the process is enlisted by the representation of it as the Law of
Nature. But, on the other hand, our respect for Laws of Nature would be speedily
diminished, did we not imagine that this desirable process was one of them. To
suppose that a Law of Nature is therefore respectable, is to commit the
naturalistic fallacy; but no one, probably, would be tempted to commit it,
unless something which is respectable, were represented as a Law of
Nature. If it were clearly recognised that there is no evidence for supposing
Nature to be on the side of the Good, there would probably be less tendency to
hold the opinion, which on other grounds is demonstrably false, that no such
evidence is required. And if both false opinions were clearly seen to be false,
it would be plain that Evolution has very little indeed to say to Ethics. (§ 34 ¶ 1)