Chapter III: Hedonism.
§ 40.
Questions
about ends,
he
says (pp. 52-3), are, in other words, questions about what things are
desirable. The utilitarian doctrine is, that happiness is desirable,
and the only thing desirable, as an end; all other things being only desirable
as means to that end. What ought to be required of this doctrine—what
conditions is it requisite that the doctrine should fulfil—to make good its
claim to be believed?
(§ 40 ¶ 1)
The only proof capable of being given that a thing is visible,
is that people actually see it. The only proof that a sound is audible, is that
people hear it; and so of the other sources of our experience. In like manner, I
apprehend, the sole evidence it is possible to produce that anything is
desirable, is that people do actually desire it. If the end which the
utilitarian doctrine proposes to itself were not, in theory and in practice,
acknowledged to be an end, nothing could ever convince any person that it was
so. No reason can be given why the general happiness is desirable, except that
each person, so far as he believes it to be attainable, desires his own
happiness. This, however, being the fact, we have not only all the proof which
the case admits of, but all which it is possible to require, that happiness is a
good: that each person’s happiness is a good to that person, and the general
happiness, therefore, a good to the aggregate of all persons. Happiness has made
out its title as one of the ends of conduct, and consequently one of
the criteria of morality.
(§ 40 ¶ 2)
There, that is enough. That is my first point. Mill has made as
naïve and artless a use of the naturalistic fallacy as anybody could desire.
Good,
he tells us, means desirable,
and you can only find out what
is desirable by seeking to find out what is actually desired. This is, of
course, only one step towards the proof of Hedonism; for it may be, as Mill goes
on to say, that other things beside pleasure are desired. Whether or not
pleasure is the only thing desired is, as
Mill himself admits (p. 58), a psychological question, to which we shall
presently proceed. The important step for Ethics is this one just taken, the
step which pretends to prove that good
means desired.
(§ 40 ¶ 3)
Well, the fallacy in this step is so obvious, that it is quite
wonderful how Mill failed to see it. The fact is that desirable
does not
mean able to be desired
as visible
means able to be seen.
The desirable means simply what ought to be desired or
deserves to be desired; just as the detestable means not what can be
but what ought to be detested and the damnable what deserves to be damned. Mill
has, then, smuggled in, under cover of the word desirable,
the very
notion about which he ought to be quite clear. Desirable
does indeed mean
what it is good to desire
; but when this is understood, it is no longer
plausible to say that our only test of that, is what is actually
desired. Is it merely a tautology when the Prayer Book talks of good
desires? Are not bad desires also possible? Nay, we find Mill himself
talking of a better and nobler object of desire
(p.
10), as if, after all, what is desired were not ipso
facto good, and good in proportion to the amount it is desired. Moreover,
if the desired is ipso facto the good; then the good
is ipso facto the motive of our actions, and there
can be no question of finding motives for doing it, as Mill is at such pains to
do. If Mill’s explanation of desirable
be true, then his
statement (p.
26) that the rule of action may be confounded with the motive of it
is untrue; for the motive of action will then be according to him ipso facto its rule; there can be no distinction between
the two, and therefore no confusion, and thus he has contradicted himself
flatly. These are specimens of the contradictions, which, as I have tried to
shew, must always follow from the use of the naturalistic fallacy; and I hope I
need now say no more about the matter. (§ 40 ¶ 4)