Chapter III: Hedonism.
§ 47.
Well, in
this connection, it seems first desirable to touch on another doctrine of
Mill’s—another doctrine which, in the interest of Hedonism,
Professor Sidgwick has done very wisely to reject. This is the doctrine of
difference of quality in pleasures.
If I am asked,
says Mill, what I mean
by difference of quality in pleasures, or what makes one pleasure more valuable
than another, merely as a pleasure, except its being greater in amount, there is
but one possible answer. Of two pleasures, if there be one to which all or
almost all who have experience of both give a decided preference, irrespective
of any feeling of moral obligation to prefer it, that is the more desirable
pleasure. If one of the two is, by those who are competantly acquainted with
both, placed so far above the other that they prefer it, even though knowing it
to be attended with a greater amount of discontent, and would not resign it for
any quantity of the other pleasure which their nature is capable of, we are
justified in ascribing to the preferred enjoyment a superiority in quality, so
far outweighing quantity as to render it, in comparison, of small account.
(§ 47 ¶ 1)
Now it is well known that Bentham rested his case for Hedonism on
quantity of pleasure
alone. It was his maxim, that quantity of
pleasure being equal, pushpin is as good as poetry.
And Mill apparently
considers Bentham to have proved that nevertheless poetry is better than
pushpin; that poetry does produce a greater quantity of pleasure. But yet,
says
Mill, the Utilitarians might have taken the other and, as it may
be called, higher ground, with entire consistency
(p.
11). Now we see from this that Mill acknowledges quality of pleasure
to be another or different ground for estimating pleasures, than Bentham’s
quantity; and moreover, by that question-begging higher,
which he
afterwards translates into superior,
he seems to betray an uncomfortable
feeling, that, after all, if you take quantity of pleasure for your only
standard, something may be wrong and you may deserve to be called a pig. And it
may presently appear that you very likely would deserve this name. But,
meanwhile, I only wish to shew that Mill’s admissions as to the quality of
pleasure are either inconsistent with his Hedonism, or else afford no other
ground for it than would be given by mere quantity of pleasure. (§ 47 ¶ 2)
It will be seen that Mill’s test for one pleasure’s superiority in
quality over another is the preference of most people who have experienced both.
A pleasure so preferred, he holds, is more desirable. But then, as we have
seen, he
holds that to think of an object as desirable and to think of it as
pleasant are one and the same thing
(p.
58). He holds,
therefore, that the preference of experts merely proves that one pleasure is
pleasanter than another. But if that is so, how can he distinguish this standard
from the standard of quantity of pleasure? Can one pleasure be pleasanter than
another, except in the sense that it gives more pleasure?
Pleasant
must, if words are to have any meaning at all, denote some one
quality common to all things that are pleasant; and, if so, then one thing can
only be more pleasant than another, according as it has more or less of this one
quality. But, then, let us try the other alternative, and suppose that Mill does
not seriously mean that this preference of experts merely proves one pleasure to
be pleasanter than another. Well, in this case, what does preferred
mean?
It cannot mean more desired,
since, as we know, the degree of desire is
always, according to Mill, in exact proportion to the degree of pleasantness.
But, in that case, the basis of Mill’s Hedonism collapses, for he is admitting
that one thing may be preferred over another, and thus proved more desirable,
although it is not more desired. In this case, Mill’s judgment of preference is
just a judgment of that intuitional kind which I have been contending to be
necessary to establish the hedonistic or any other principle. It is a direct
judgment that one thing is more desirable, or better than another; a judgment
utterly independent of all considerations as to whether one thing is more
desired or pleasanter than another. This is to admit that good is good and
indefinable. (§ 47 ¶ 3)