Chapter III: Hedonism.
§ 50.
The passages in the Methods of Ethics to which I shall now invite attention are to be found in I. IX. 4 and in III. XIV. 4—5. (§ 50 ¶ 1)
The first of these two passages runs as follows:(§ 50 ¶ 2)
I think that if we consider carefully such permanent results as are commonly judged to be good, other than qualities of human beings, we can find nothing that, on reflection, appears to possess this quality of goodness out of relation to human existence, or at least to some consciousness or feeling. (§ 50 ¶ 3)
For example, we commonly judge some inanimate objects, scenes, etc. to be good as possessing beauty, and others bad from ugliness: still no one would consider it rational to aim at the production of beauty in external nature, apart from any possible contemplation of it by human beings. In fact when beauty is maintained to be objective, it is not commonly meant that it exists as beauty out of relation to any mind whatsoever: but only that there is some standard of beauty valid for all minds. (§ 50 ¶ 4)
It may, however, be said that beauty and other results commonly judged to be good, though we do not conceive them to exist out of relation to human beings (or at least minds of some kind), are yet so far separable as ends from the human beings on whom their existence depends, that their realisation may conceivably come into competition with the perfection or happiness of these beings. Thus, though beautiful things cannot be thought worth producing except as possible objects of contemplation, still a man may devote himself to their production without any consideration of the persons who are to contemplate them. Similarly knowledge is a good which cannot exist except in minds; and yet one may be more interested in the development of knowledge than in its possession by any particular minds; and may take the former as an ultimate end without regarding the latter. (§ 50 ¶ 5)
Still, as soon as the alternatives are clearly apprehended, it will, I think, be generally held that beauty, knowledge, and other ideal goods, as well as all external material things, are only reasonably to be sought by men in so far as they conduce either (1) to Happiness or (2) to the Perfection or Excellence of human existence. I say
human,for though most utilitarians consider the pleasure (and freedom from pain) of the inferior animals to be included in the Happiness which they take as the right and proper end of conduct, no one seems to contend that we ought to aim at perfecting brutes, except as a means to our ends, or at least as objects of scientific or aesthetic contemplation for us. Nor, again, can we include, as a practical end, the existence of beings above the human. We certainly apply the idea of Good to the Divine Existence, just as we do to His work, and indeed in a pre-eminent manner: and when it is said thatwe should do all things to the glory of God,it may seem to be implied that the existence of God is made better by our glorifying Him. Still this inference when explicitly drawn appears somewhat impious and theologians generally recoil from it, and refrain from using the notion of a possible addition to the Goodness of the Divine Existence as a ground of human duty. Nor can the influence of our actions on other extra-human intelligences besides the Divine be at present made matter of scientific discussion. (§ 50 ¶ 6)I shall therefore confidently lay down, that if there be any Good other than Happiness to be sought by man, as an ultimate practical end, it can only be the Goodness, Perfection, or Excellence of Human Existence. How far this notion includes more than Virtue, what its precise relation to Pleasure is, and to what method we shall be logically led if we accept it as fundamental, are questions which we shall more conveniently discuss after the detailed examination of these two other notions, Pleasure and Virtue, in which we shall be engaged in the two following Books. (§ 50 ¶ 7)
It will be observed that in this passage Prof. Sidgwick tries to limit the range of objects among which the ultimate end may be found. He does not yet say what that end is, but he does exclude from it everything but certain characters of Human Existence. And the possible ends, which he thus excludes, do not again come up for consideration. They are put out of court once and for all by this passage and by this passage only. Now is this exclusion justified?(§ 50 ¶ 8)
I cannot think it is. No one,
says
Prof. Sidgwick, would consider it rational to aim at the production of
beauty in external nature, apart from any possible contemplation of it by human
beings.
Well, I may say at once, that I, for one, do consider this rational;
and let us see if I cannot get any one to agree with me. Consider what this
admission really means. It entitles us to put the following case. Let us imagine
one world exceedingly beautiful. Imagine it as beautiful as you can; put into it
whatever on this earth you most admire—mountains, rivers, the sea; trees, and
sunsets, stars and moon. Imagine these all combined in the most exquisite
proportions, so that no one thing jars against another, but each contributes to
the beauty of the whole. And then imagine the ugliest world you can possibly
conceive. Imagine it simply one heap of filth, containing everything that is
most disgusting to us, for whatever reason, and the whole, as far as may be,
without one redeeming feature. Such a pair of worlds we are entitled to compare:
they fall within Prof. Sidgwick’s meaning, and the comparison is highly relevant
to it. The only thing we are not entitled to imagine is that any human being
ever has or ever, by any possibility, can, live in either, can ever see
and enjoy the beauty of the one or hate the foulness of the other. Well, even
so, supposing them quite apart from any possible contemplation by human beings;
still, is it irrational to hold that it is better that the beautiful world
should exist than the one which is ugly? Would it not be well, in any case, to
do what we could to produce it rather than the other? Certainly I cannot help
thinking that it would; and I hope that some may agree with me in this extreme
instance. The instance is extreme. It is highly improbable, not to say,
impossible, we should ever have such a choice before us. In any actual choice we
should have to consider the possible effects of our action upon conscious
beings, and among these possible effects there are always some, I think, which
ought to be preferred to the existence of mere beauty. But this only means that
in our present state, in which but a very small portion of the good is
attainable, the pursuit of beauty for its own sake must always be postponed to
the pursuit of some greater good, which is equally attainable. But it is enough
for my purpose, if it be admitted that, supposing no greater good were
at all attainable, then beauty must in itself be regarded as a greater good than
ugliness; if it be admitted that, in that case, we should not be left without
any reason for preferring one course of action to another, we should not be left
without any duty whatever, but that it would then be our positive duty to make
the world more beautiful, so far as we were able, since nothing better than
beauty could then result from our efforts. If this be once admitted, if in any
imaginable case you do admit that the existence of a more beautiful thing is
better in itself than that of one more ugly, quite apart from its effects on any
human feeling, then Prof. Sidgwick’s principle has broken down. Then we shall
have to include in our ultimate end something beyond the limits of human
existence. I admit, of course, that our beautiful world would be better still,
if there were human beings in it to contemplate and enjoy its beauty. But that
admission makes nothing against my point. If it be once admitted that the
beautiful world in itself is better than the ugly, then it follows,
that however many beings may enjoy it, and however much better their enjoyment
may be than it is itself, yet its mere existence adds something to the
goodness of the whole: it is not only a means to our end, but also itself a part
thereof. (§ 50 ¶ 9)