Chapter IV: Metaphysical Ethics.
§ 70.
And, first of
all, there is an ambiguity in the very question: What is good? to which it seems
some influence must be attributed. The question may mean either: Which among
existing things are good? or else: What sort of things are good, what
are the things which, whether they are real or not, ought to be real?
And of these two questions it is plain that to answer the first, we must know
both the answer to the second and also the answer to this question: What is
real? It asks us for a catalogue of all the good things there are in the
Universe and also which of them are good. Upon this question then our
Metaphysics would have a bearing, if it can tell us what is real. It would help
us to complete the list of things which are both real and good. But to make such
a list is not the business of Ethics. So far as it enquires What is good? its
business is finished when it has completed the list of things which ought to
exist, whether they do exist or not. And if our Metaphysics is to have any
bearing upon this part of the ethical problem, it must be because the fact that
something is real gives a reason for thinking that it or something else is good,
whether it be real or not. That any such fact can give any such reason is
impossible; but it may be suspected that the contrary supposition has been
encouraged by the failure to distinguish between the assertion This is
good,
when it means This sort of thing is good,
or This
would be good, if it existed,
and the assertion This existing thing is
good.
The latter proposition obviously cannot be true, unless the thing
exists; and hence the proof of the thing's existence is a necessary step to its
proof. Both propositions, however, in spite of this immense difference between
them, are commonly expressed in the same terms. We use the same words, when we
assert an ethical proposition about a subject that is actually real, and when we
assert it about a subject considered as merely possible. (§ 70 ¶ 1)
In this ambiguity of language we have, then, a possible source of
error with regard to the bearing of truths that assert reality upon truths that
assert goodness. And that this ambiguity is actually neglected by those
metaphysical writers who profess that the Supreme Good consists in an eternal
reality may be shewn in the following way. We have seen, in considering the
possible bearing of Metaphysics upon Practical Ethics, that, since what exists
eternally cannot possibly be affected by our actions, no practical maxim can
possibly be true, if the sole reality is eternal. This fact, as I said, is
commonly neglected by metaphysical writers: they assert both of the two
contradictory propositions that the sole reality is eternal and that its
realisation in the future is a good too. Prof. Mackenzie, we saw, asserts that
we ought to aim at the realisation of the true self
or the rational
universe
: and yet Prof. Mackenzie holds, as the word true
plainly
implies, that both the true self
and the rational universe
are
eternally real. Here we have already a contradiction in the supposition that
what is eternally real can be realised in the future; and it is comparatively
unimportant whether or not we add to this the further contradiction involved in
the supposition that the eternal is the sole reality. That such a contradiction
should be supposed valid can only be explained by a neglect of the distinction
between a real subject and the character which that real subject possesses.
What is eternally real may, indeed, be realised in the future, if by
this be only meant the sort of thing which is eternally real. But when
we assert that a thing is good, what we mean is that its existence or reality is
good; and the eternal existence of a thing cannot possibly be the same good as
the existence in time of what, in a necessary sense, is nevertheless the
same thing. When, therefore, we are told that the future realisation of
the true self is good, this can at most only mean that the future
realisation of a self exactly like the self, which is true and exists
eternally, is good. If this fact were clearly stated, instead of consistently
ignored, by those who advocate the view that the Supreme Good can be defined in
these metaphysical terms, it seems probable that the view that a knowledge of
reality is necessary to a knowledge of the Supreme Good would lose part of its
plausibility. That that at which we ought to aim cannot possibly be that which
is eternally real, even if it be exactly like it; and that the eternal reality
cannot possibly be the sole good—these two propositions seem sensibly to
diminish the probability that Ethics must be based on Metaphysics. It is not
very plausible to maintain that because one thing is real, therefore something
like it, which is not real, would be good. It seems, therefore, that some of the
plausibility of Metaphysical Ethics may be reasonably attributed to the failure
to observe that verbal ambiguity, whereby This is good
may mean either
This real thing is good
or The existence of this thing (whether it
exists or not) would be good.
(§ 70
¶ 2)