Chapter V: Ethics in Relation to Conduct.
§ 86.
In the present
chapter we have again to take a great step in ethical method. My discussion
hitherto has fallen under two main heads. Under the first, I tried to shew what
good
—the adjective good
—means. This appeared to be the
first point to be settled in any treatment of Ethics, that should aim at being
systematic. It is necessary we should know this, should know what good means,
before we can go on to consider what is good—what things or qualities are good.
It is necessary we should know it for two reasons. The first reason is that
good
is the notion upon which all Ethics depends. We cannot hope to
understand what we mean, when we say that this is good or that is good, until we
understand quite clearly, not only what this
is or that
is (which
the natural sciences and philosophy can tell us) but also what is meant by
calling them good, a matter which is reserved for Ethics only. Unless we are
quite clear on this point, our ethical reasoning will be always apt to be
fallacious. We shall think that we are proving that a thing is good,
when
we are really only proving that it is something else; since unless we know what
good
means, unless we know what is meant by that notion in itself, as
distinct from what is meant by any other notion, we shall not be able to tell
when we are dealing with it and when we are dealing with something else, which
is perhaps like it, but yet not the same. And the second reason why we should
settle first of all this question What good means?
is a reason of method.
It is this, that we can never know on what evidence an ethical
proposition rests, until we know the nature of the notion which makes the
proposition ethical. We cannot tell what is possible, by way of proof, in favour
of one judgment that This or that is good,
or against another judgment
That this or that is bad,
until we have recognised what the nature of
such propositions must always be. In fact, it follows from the meaning of good
and bad, that such propositions are all of them, in Kant's phrase,
synthetic
: they all must rest in the end upon some proposition which must
be simply accepted or rejected, which cannot be logically deduced from any other
proposition. This result, which follows from our first investigation, may be
otherwise expressed by saying that the fundamental principles of Ethics must be
self-evident. But I am anxious that this expression should not be misunderstood.
The expression self-evident
means properly that the proposition so called
is evident or true, by itself alone; that it is not an inference from
some proposition other than itself. The expression does not
mean that the proposition is true, because it is evident to you or me or all
mankind, because in other words it appears to us to be true. That a proposition
appears to be true can never be a valid argument that true it really is. By
saying that a proposition is self-evident, we mean emphatically that its
appearing so to us, is not the reason why it is true: for we mean that
it has absolutely no reason. It would not be a self-evident proposition, if we
could say of it: I cannot think otherwise and therefore it is true. For then its
evidence or proof would not lie in itself, but in something else, namely our
conviction of it. That it appears true to us may indeed be the cause of
our asserting it, or the reason why we think and say that it is true: but a
reason in this sense is something utterly different from a logical reason, or
reason why something is true. Moreover, it is obviously not a reason of the same
thing. The evidence of a proposition to us is only a reason for our
holding it to be true: whereas a logical reason, or reason in the sense in
which self-evident propositions have no reason, is a reason why the
proposition itself must be true, not why we hold it so to be. Again that a
proposition is evident to us may not only be the reason why we do think or
affirm it, it may even be a reason why we ought to think it or affirm
it. But a reason, in this sense too, is not a logical reason for the truth of
the proposition, though it is a logical reason for the rightness of holding the
proposition. In our common language, however, these three meanings of
reason
are constantly confused, whenever we say I have a reason for
thinking that true.
But it is absolutely essential, if we are to get clear
notions about Ethics or, indeed, about any other, especially any philosophical,
study, that we should distinguish them. When, therefore, I talk of
Intuitionistic Hedonism, I must not be understood to imply that my denial that
Pleasure is the only good
is based on my Intuition of its
falsehood. My intuition of its falsehood is indeed my reason for
holding and declaring it untrue; it is indeed the only valid reason for
so doing. But that is just because there is no logical reason for it;
because there is no proper evidence or reason of its falsehood except itself
alone. It is untrue, because it is untrue, and there is no other reason: but I
declare it untrue, because its untruth is evident to me, and I hold
that that is a sufficient reason for my assertion. We must not therefore look on
Intuition, as if it were an alternative to reasoning. Nothing whatever can take
the place of reasons for the truth of any proposition: intuition can
only furnish a reason for holding any proposition to be true: this
however it must do when any proposition is self-evident, when, in fact, there
are no reasons which prove its truth. (§ 86
¶ 1)
§ 87.
So much, then, for
the first step which established that good is good and nothing else whatever,
and that Naturalism was a fallacy. A second step was taken when we began to
consider proposed self-evident principles of Ethics. In this second division,
resting on our result that good means good, we began the discussion of
propositions asserting that such and such a thing or quality or concept was
good. Of such a kind was the principle of Intuitionistic or Ethical
Hedonism—the principle that Pleasure alone is good.
Following the method
established by our first discussion, I claimed that the untruth of this
proposition was self-evident. I could do nothing to prove that it was
untrue; I could only point out as clearly as possible what it means, and how it
contradicts other propositions which appear to be equally true. My only object
in all this was, necessarily, to convince. But even if I did convince, that does
not prove that we are right. It justifies us in holding that we are so;
but nevertheless we may be wrong. On one thing, however, we may justly pride
ourselves. It is that we have had a better chance of answering our questions
rightly, than Bentham or Mill or Sidgwick or others who have contradicted us.
For we have proved that these have never even asked themselves the
question which they professed to answer. They have confused it with another
question: small wonder, therefore, if their answer is different from ours. We
must be quite sure that the same question has been put, before we trouble
ourselves at the different answers that are given to it. For all we know, the
whole world would agree with us, if they could once clearly understand the
question upon which we want their votes. Certain it is, that in all those cases
where we found a difference of opinion, we found also that the question had
not been clearly understood. Though, therefore, we cannot prove that we
are right, yet we have a reason to believe that everybody, unless he is mistaken
as to what he thinks, will think the same as we. It is as with a sum in
mathematics. If we find a gross and palpable error in the calculations, we are
not surprised or troubled that the person who made this mistake has reached a
different result from ours. We think he will admit that his result is wrong, if
his mistake is pointed out to him. For instance if a man has to add up 5 + 7 +
9, we should not wonder that he made the result to be 34, if he started by
making 5 + 7 = 25. And so in Ethics, if we find, as we did, that
desirable
is confused with desired,
or that end
is confused
with means,
we need not be disconcerted that those who have committed
these mistakes do not agree with us. The only difference is that in Ethics,
owing to the intricacy of its subject matter, it is far more difficult to
persuade anyone either that he has made a mistake or that that mistake affects
his result. (§ 87 ¶ 1)
In this second division of my subject—the division which is
occupied with the question, What is good in itself?
—I have hitherto only
tried to establish one definite result, and that a negative one: namely that
pleasure is not the sole good. This result, if true, refutes half, or
more than half, of the ethical theories which have ever been held, and is,
therefore, not without importance. It will, however, be necessary presently to
deal positively with the question: What things are good and in what degrees? (§ 87 ¶ 2)
§ 88.
But before proceeding to this discussion I propose, first, to deal with the third kind of ethical question—the quesiton: What ought we to do? (§ 88 ¶ 1)
The answering of this question constitutes the third great division of ethical enquiry; and its nature was briefly explained in Chap. I (§§ 15—17). It introduces into Ethics, as was there pointed out, an entirely new question—the question what things are related as causes to that which is good in itself; and this question can only be answered by an entirely new method—the method of empirical investigation; by means of which causes are discovered in the other sciences. To ask what kind of actions we ought to perform, or what kind of conduct is right, is to ask what kind of effects such action and conduct will produce. Not a single question in practical Ethics can be answered except by a causal generalisation. All such questions do, indeed, also involve an ethical judgment proper—the judgment that certain effects are better, in themselves, than others. But they do assert that these better things are effects—are causally connected with the actions in question. Every judgment in practical Ethics may be reduced to the form: This is a cause of that good thing. (§ 88 ¶ 2)