Introduction: The Idea of a Natural Science of Morals.
§5.
It is no wonder, therefore, that the evolutionists of our day should claim to
have given a wholly new character to ethical enquiries. In Hume’s time a
philosopher who denied the innateness of moral sentiments, and held that they
must have a natural history, had only the limits of the individual life within
which to trace this history. These limits did not give room enough for even a
plausible derivation of moral interests from animal wants. It is otherwise when
the history may be supposed to range over an indefinite number of generations.
The doctrine of hereditary transmission, it is held, explains to us how
susceptibilities of pleasure and pain, of desire and aversion, of hope and fear,
may be handed down with gradually accumulated modifications which in time attain
the full measure of the difference between the moral man and the greater ape.
Through long ages of interaction between the human organism and the social
medium in which it lives, there has been developed that sensibility of
principle which feels a stain like a wound;
that faculty of moral intuition
which not only pronounces unerringly on the social tendencies of the commonest
forms of human action, but enables us in some measure to see ourselves as others
see us; that civil spirit through which the promptings of personal passion are
controlled even in the individual by the larger vision and calmer interest of
society. (§5 ¶1)
Thus it would seem that for the barren speculation of the old metaphysical
ethics we should seek a substitute in a scientific Culturgeschichte
; in a natural history of man conducted on the
same method as an enquiry into any other form of life which cannot be reduced to
the operation of strictly mechanical laws. For the later stages of this history
we have, of course, abundant materials in the actual monuments of human
culture—linguistic, literary, and legal—and these, the physiologist may say,
have yet to be considered in connexion with the data which his own science
furnishes. It is true that, however far they carry us back, however great the
variations of moral sentiment to which they testify, they do not bring us to a
state of things in which the essential conditions of that sentiment were absent.
The most primitive man they may exhibit to us is already conscious of his own
good as conditioned by that of others, alrseady capable of recognising an
obligation. But the theory of descent and evolution opens up a vista of
possibilities beyond the facts, so far ascertained, of human history, and
suggests an enquiry into the antecedents of the moralised man based on other
data than the records which he has left of himself. Such enquiry, it is thought,
will in time give us the means of reducing the moral susceptibilities of man to
the rank of ordinary physical facts, parts of one system, and intelligible by
the same methods, with all the natural phenomena which we are learning to know.
Man will then have his ascertained place in nature, as perhaps the noblest of
the animals, but an animal still. (§5 ¶2)