Essay IV, n. 1: Extract from an article entitled A World of Pure Experience, in the Journal of Philosophy, etc., September 29, 1904.
Throughout the history of philosophy the subject and its object
have been treated as absolutely discontinuous entities; and thereupon the
presence of the latter to the former, or the apprehension
by the former
of the latter, has assumed a paradoxical character which all sorts of theories
had to be invented to overcome. Representative theories put a mental
representation,
image,
or content
into the gap, as a sort
of intermediary. Common-sense theories left the gap untouched, declaring our
mind able to clear it by a self-transcending leap. Transcendentalist theories
left it impossible to traverse by finite knowers, and brought an Absolute in to
perform the saltatory act. All the while, in the very bosom of the finite
experience, every conjunction required to make the relation intelligible is
given in full. Either the knower and the known are: (Essay IV ¶ 1)
the self-same piece of experience taken twice over in different contexts; or they are (Essay IV ¶ 2)
two pieces of actual experience belonging to the same subject, with definite tracts of conjunctive transitional experience between them; or (Essay IV ¶ 3)
the known is a possible experience either of that subject or another, to which the said conjunctive transitions would lead, if sufficiently prolonged. (Essay IV ¶ 4)
To discuss all the ways in which one experience may function as the
knower of another, would be incompatible with the limits of this essay. I have
just treated of type 1, the kind of knowledge called perception, in an article
in the Journal of Philosophy, for Septembe 1, 1904,
called Does consciousness exist? This is the type of case in
which the mind enjoys direct acquaintance
with a present object. In the
other types the mind has knowledge-about
an object not immediately there.
Type 3 can always formally and hypothetically be reduced to type 2, so that a
brief description of that type will put the present reader sufficiently at my
point of view, and make him see what the actual meanings of the mysterious
cognitive relation may be. (Essay IV ¶ 5)
Suppose me to be sitting here in my library
at Cambridge, at ten minutes’ walk from
Memorial Hall,
and to be thinking truly of
the latter object. My mind may have before
it only the name, or it may have a clear image,
or it may have a very dim image of the hall, but
such intrinsic differences in the image make no
difference in its cognitive function. Certain
extrinsic phenomena, special experiences of
conjunction, are what impart to the image, be
it what it may, its knowing office. (Essay IV ¶ 6)
For instance, if you ask me what hall I mean
by my image, and I call tell you nothing; or if I
fail to point or lead you towards the Harvard
Delta; or if, being led by you, I am uncertain
whether the Hall I see be what I had in mind
or not; you would rightly deny that I had
meant
that particular hall at all, even tho
my mental image might to some degree have
resembled it. The resemblance would count in
that case as coincidental merely, for all sorts
of things of a kind resemble one another in this
world without being held for that reason to
take cognizance of one another. (Essay IV ¶ 7)
On the other hand, if I can lead you to the hall, and tell you of its history and present uses; if in its presence I feel my idea, however imperfect it may have been, to have led hither and to be now terminated; if the associates of the image and of the felt hall run parallel, so that each term of the one context corresponds serially, as I walk, with an answering term of the others; why then my soul was prophetic, and my idea must be, and by common consent would be, called cognizant of reality. That percept was what I meant, for into it my idea has passed by conjunctive experiences of sameness and fulfilled intention. Nowhere is there jar, but every later moment continues and corroborates an earlier one. (Essay IV ¶ 8)
In this continuing and corroborating, taken
in no transcendental sense, but denoting definitely
felt transitions, lies all that the knowing
of a percept by an idea can possibly contain or
signify. Wherever such transitions are felt, the
first experience knows that last one. Where they
do not, or where even as possibles they can not,
intervene, there can be no pretence of knowing.
In this latter case the extremes will be connected,
if connected at all, by inferior relations
— bare likeness or succession, or by withness
alone. Knowledge of sensible realities thus
comes to life inside the tissue of experience. It
is made; and made by relations that unroll
themselves in time. Whenever certain intermediaries
are given, such that, as they develop
towards their terminus, there is experience
from point to point of one direction followed,
and finally of one process fulfilled, the result
is that their starting-point thereby becomes a
knower and their terminus an object meant or
known. That is all that knowing (in the simple
case considered) can be known-as, that is
the whole of its nature, put into experiential
terms. Whenever such is the sequence of our
experiences we may freely say that we had the
terminal object in mind
from the outset, even
although at the outset nothing was there in us
but a flat piece of substantive experience like
any other, with no self-transcendency about it,
and ny mystery save the mystery of coming
into existence and of being gradually followed
by other pieces of substantive experience, with
conjunctively transitional experiences between.
That is what we mean here by the object’s
being in mind.
Of any deeper more real way
of being in mind we have no positive conception,
and we have no right to discredit our
actual experience by talking of such a way
at all. (Essay IV ¶ 9)
I know that many a reader will rebel at this.
Mere intermediaries,
he will say, even
though they be feelings of continuously growing
fulfilment, only separate the knower from
the known, whereas what we have in knowledge
is a kind of immediate touch of the one by the
other, an
(Essay IV ¶ 10)apprehension
in the etymological
sense of the word, a leaping of the chasm as by
lightning, an act by which two terms are smitten
into one, over the head of their distinctness.
All these dead intermediaries of yours
are out of each other, and outside of their
termini still.
But do not such dialectic difficulties remind
us of the dog dropping his bone and snapping
at its image in the water? If we knew any more
real kind of union aliunde, we might be entitled
to brand all our empirical unions as a sham.
But unions by continuous transition are the
only ones we know of, whether in this matter
of a knowledge-about that terminates in an
acquaintance, whether in personal identity, in
logical predication through the copula is,
or
elsewhere. If anywhere there were more absolute
unions realized, they could only reveal
themselves to us by just such conjunctive
results. These are what the unions are worth,
these are all that we can ever practically mean
by union, by continuity. Is it not time to
repeat what Lotze said of substances, that to
act like one is to be one? Should we not say
here that to be experienced as continuous is to
be really continuous, in a world where experience
and reality come to the same thing? In
a picture gallery a painted hook will serve to
hang a painted chain by, a painted cable will
hold a painted ship. In a world where both the
terms and their distinctions are affairs of experience,
conjunctions that are experienced
must be at least as real as anything else. They
will be absolutely
real conjunctions, if we have
no transphenomenal Absolute ready, to derealize
the whole experienced world by, at a stroke. (Essay IV ¶ 11)
So much for the essentials of the cognitive
relation, where the knowledge is conceptual in
type, or forms knowledge about
an object. It
consists in intermediary experiences (possible,
if not actual) of continuously developing progress,
and, finally, of fulfilment, when the sensible
percept, which is the object, is reached.
The percept here not only verifies the concept,
proves its function of knowing that percept to
be true, but the percept’s existence as the
terminus of the chain of intermediaries creates
the function. Whatever terminates that chain
was, because it now proves itself to be, what
the concept had in mind.
(Essay IV ¶ 12)
The towering importance for human life of
this kind of knowing lies in the fact that an
experience that knows another can figure as
its representative, not in any quasi-miraculous
epistemological
sense, but in the definite
practical sense of being its substitute in various
operations, sometimes physical and sometimes
mental, which lead us to its associates and results.
By experimenting on our ideas of reality,
we may save ourselves the trouble of experimenting
on the real experiences which they
severally mean. The ideas form related systems,
corresponding point for point to the systems
which the realities form; and by letting an
ideal term call up its associates systematically,
we may be led to a terminus which the corresponding
real term would have led to in case
we had operated on the real world. And this
brings us to the general question of substitution. (Essay IV ¶ 13)
What, exactly, in a system of experiences, does
the substitution
of one of them for another
mean? (Essay IV ¶ 14)
According to my view, experience as a whole
is a process in time, whereby innumerable
particular terms lapse and are superseded by
others that follow upon them by transitions
which, whether disjunctive or conjunctive in
content, are themselves experiences, and must
in general be accounted at least as real as
the terms which they relate. What the nature
of the event called superseding
signifies, depends
altogether on the kind of transition
that obtains. Some experiences simply abolish
their predecessors without continuing them
in any way. Others are felt to increase or to
enlarge their meaning, to carry out their purpose,
or to bring us nearer to their goal. They
represent
them, and may fulfil their function
better than they fulfilled it themselves. But to
fulfil a function
in a world of pure experience
can be conceived and defined in only one possible
way. In such a world transitions and
arrivals (or terminations) are the only events
that happen, tho they happen by so many
sorts of path. The only experience that one experience
can perform is to lead into another
experience; and the only fulfilment we can
speak of is the reaching of a certain experienced
end. When one experience leads to (or
can lead to) the same end as another, they
agree in function. But the whole system of
experiences as they are immediately given
presents itself as a quasi-chaos through which
one can pass out of an initial term in many
directions and yet end in the same terminus,
moving from next to next by a great many
possible paths. (Essay IV ¶ 15)
Either one of these paths might be a functional
substitute for another, and to follow one
rather than another might on occasion be
an advantageous thing to do. As a matter of
fact, and in a general way, the paths that
run through conceptual experiences, that is,
through thoughts
or ideas
that know
the
things in which they terminate, are highly advantageous
paths to follow. Not only do they
yield inconceivably rapid transitions; but, owing
to the universal
character which they
frequently possess, and to their capacity for
association with one another in great systems,
they outstrip the tardy consecutions of the
things themselves, and sweep us on towards
our ultimate termini in a far more labor-saving
way than the following of trains of sensible
perception ever could. Wonderful are the new
cuts and the short-circuits which the thought-
paths make. Most thought-paths, it is true,
are substitutes for nothing actual; they end
outside the real world altogether, in wayward
fancies, utopias, fictions or mistakes. But
where they do re-enter reality and terminate
therein, we substitute them always; and with
these substitutes we pass the greater number
of our hours. (Essay IV ¶ 16)
Whosoever feels his experience to be something
substitutional even while he has it, may
be said to have an experience that reaches
beyond itself. From inside of its own entity it
says more,
and postulates reality existing elsewhere.
For the transcendentalist, who holds
knowing to consist in a salto mortale across an
epistemological chasm,
such an idea presents
no difficulty; but it seems at first sight as if it
might be inconsistent with an empiricism like
our own. Have we not explained that conceptual
knowledge is made such wholly by the
existence of things that fall outside of the
knowing experience itself — by intermediary
experience and by a terminus that fulfils?
Can the knowledge be there before these elements
that constitute its being have come?
And, if knowledge be not there, how can objective
reference occur? (Essay IV ¶ 17)
The key to this difficulty lies in the distinction
between knowing as verified and completed,
and the same knowing as in transit
and on its way. To recur to the Memorial
Hall example lately used, it is only when our
idea of the Hall has actually terminated in the
percept that we know for certain
that from
the beginning it was truly cognitive of that.
Until established by the end of the process, its
quality of knowing that, or indeed of knowing
anything, could still be doubted; and yet the
knowing really was there, as the result now
shows. We were virtual knowers of the Hall
long before we were certified to have been its
actual knowers, by the percept’s retroactive
validating power. Just so we are mortal
all
the time, by reason of the virtuality of the
inevitable event which will make us so when
it shall have come. (Essay IV ¶ 18)
Now the immensely greater part of all our
knowing never gets beyond this virtual stage.
It never is completed or nailed down. I speak
not merely of our ideas of imperceptibles like
ether-waves or dissociated ions,
or of ejects
like the contents of our neighbors’ minds; I
speak also of ideas which we might verify if we
would take the trouble, but which we hold for
true altho unterminated perceptually, because
nothing says no
to us, and there is no
contradicting truth in sight. To continue thinking
unchallenged is, ninety-nine times out of a
hundred, our practical substitute for knowing in
the completed sense. As each experience runs by
cognitive transition into the next one, and we
nowhere feel a collision with what we elsewhere
count as truth or fact, we commit ourselves to
the current as if the port were sure. We live,
as it were, upon the front edge of an advancing
wave-crest, and our sense of a determinate
direction in falling forward is all we cover of
the future of our path. It is as if a differential
quotient should be conscious and treat itself as
an adequate substitute for a traced-out curve.
Our experience, inter alia, is of variations of
rate and of direction, and lives in these transitions
more than in the journey’s end. The experiences
of tendency are sufficient to act upon
— what more could we have done at those
moments even if the later verification comes
complete? (Essay IV ¶ 19)
This is what, as a radical empiricist, I say to
the charge that the objective reference which
is so flagrant a character of our experience involves
a chasm and a mortal leap. A positively
conjunctive transition involves neither chasm
nor leap. Being the very original of what we
mean by continuity, it makes a continuum
wherever it appears. Objective reference is an incident
of the fact that so much of our experience
comes as an insufficient and consists of
process and transition. Our fields of experience
have no more definite boundaries than have
our fields of view. Both are fringed forever by
a more that continuously develops, and that
continuously supersedes them as life proceeds.
The relations, generally speaking, are as real
here as the terms are, and the only complaint
of the transcendentalist’s with which I could
at all sympathize would be his charge that, by
first making knowledge consist in external
relations as I have done, and by then confessing
that nine-tenths of the time these are
not actually but only virtually there, I have
knocked the solid bottom out of the whole
business, and palmed off a substitute of knowledge
for the genuine thing. Only the admission,
such a critic might say, that our ideas are
self-transcendent and true
already, in advance
of the experiences that are to terminate
them, can bring solidity back to knowledge
in a world like this, in which transitions and
terminations are only by exception fulfilled. (Essay IV ¶ 20)
This seems to me an excellent place for applying the pragmatic method. What would the self-transcendency affirmed to exist in advance of all experiential mediation or termination, be known-as? What would it practically result in for us, were it true? (Essay IV ¶ 21)
It could only result in our orientation, in the
turning of our expectations and practical tendencies
into the right path; and the right path
here, so long as we and the object are not yet
face to face (or can never get face to face, as in
the case of ejects), would be the path that led
us into the object’s nearest neighborhood.
Where direct acquaintance is lacking, knowledge
about
is the next best thing, and an
acquaintance with what actually lies about the
object, and is most closely related to it, puts
such knowledge within our gasp. Ether-waves
and your anger, for example, are things in
which my thoughts will never perceptually terminate,
but my concepts of them lead me to
their very brink, to the chromatic fringes and
to the hurtful words and deeds which are their
really next effects. (Essay IV ¶ 22)
Even if our ideas did in themselves possess the postulated self-transcendency, it would still remain true that their putting us into possession of such effects would be the sole cash-value of the self-transcendency for us. And this cash-value, it is needless to say, is verbatim et literatim what our empiricist account pays in. On pragmatist principles, therefore, a dispute over self-transcendency is a pure logomachy. Call our concepts of ejective things self-transcendent or the reverse, it makes no difference, so long as we don’t differ about the nature of that exalted virtue’s fruits — fruits for us, of course, humanistic fruits. (Essay IV ¶ 23)
The transcendentalist believes his ideas to be self-transcendent only because he finds that in fact they do bear fruits. Why need he quarrel with an account of knowledge that insists on naming this effect? Why not treat the working of the idea from next to next as the essence of self-transcendency? Why insist that knowing is a static relation out of time when it practically seems so much a function of our active life? For a thing to be valid, says Lotze, is the same as to make itself valid. When the whole universe seems only to be making itself valid and to be still incomplete (else why its ceaseless changing?) why, of all things, should knowing be exempt? Why should it not be making itself valid like everything else? That some parts of it may be already valid or verified beyond dispute, the empirical philosopher, of course, like any one else, may always hope. (Essay IV ¶ 24)
Essay IV, n. 2: Of which all that need be said in this essay is that it also can be conceived as functional, and defined in terms of transitions, or of the possibility of such. ↩
Essay IV, n. 3: This is why I called our experiences, taken
together, a quasi-chaos. There is vastly
more discontinuity in the sum total of experiences
than we commonly suppose. The objective
nucleus of every man’s experience, his own
body, is, it is true, a continuous percept; and
equally c??ontinuous as a percept (thought we
may be inattentive to it) is the material environment
of that body, changing by gradual
transition when the body moves. But the
distant parts of the physical world are at all
times absent from us, and form conceptual
objects merely, into the perceptual reality of
which our life inserts itself at points discrete
and relatively rare. Round their several objective
nuclei, partly shared and common and
partly discrete, of the real physical world, innumerable
thinkers, pursuing their several lines
of physically true cogitation, trace paths that
intersect one another only at discontinuous
perceptual points, and the rest of the time are
quite incongruent; and around all the nuclei
of shared reality
floats the vast cloud of
experiences that are wholly subjective, that
are non-substitutional, that find not even an
eventual ending for themselves in the perceptual
world — there mere day-dreams and
joys and sufferings and wishes of the individual
minds. These exist with one another, indeed,
and with the objective nuclei, but out
of them it is probable that to all eternity no
interrelated system of any kind will every be
made. ↩