Chapter VI: The Ideal.
§ 112.
The method which must be
employed in order to decide the question What things have intrinsic value,
and in what degrees?
has already been explained in Chap.
III. (§§ 55, 57). In order to arrive at a correct decision on the first part
of this question, it is necessary to consider what things are such that, if they
existed by themselves, in absolute isolation, we should yet judge their
existence to be good; and, in order to decide upon the relative degrees
of value of different things, we must similarly consider what comparative value
seems to attach to the isolated existence of each. By employing this method, we
shall guard against two errors, which seem to have been the chief causes which
have vitiated previous conclusions on the subject. The first of these is (1)
that which consists in supposing that what seems absolutely necessary here and
now, for the existence of anything good—what we cannot do without—is therefore
good in itself. If we isolate such things, which are mere means to good, and
suppose a world in which they alone, and nothing but they, existed, their
intrinsic worthlessness becomes apparent. And, secondly, there is the more
subtle error (2) which consists in neglecting the principle of organic unities.
This error is committed, when it is supposed, that, if one part of a whole has
no intrinsic value, the value of the whole must reside entirely in the other
parts. It has, in this way, been commonly supposed, that, if all valuable wholes
could be seen to have one and only one common property, the wholes must be
valuable solely because they possess this property; and the illusion is
greatly strengthened, if the common property in question seems, considered by
itself, to have more value than the other parts of such wholes, considered by
themselves. But, if we consider the property in question, in isolation,
and then compare it with the whole, of which it forms a part, it may become
easily apparent that, existing by itself, the property in question has not
nearly so much value, as has the whole to which it belongs. Thus, if we compare
the value of a certain amount of pleasure, existing absolutely by
itself, with the value of certain enjoyments,
containing an equal
amount of pleasure, it may become apparent that the enjoyment
is much
better than the pleasure, and also, in some cases, much worse. In such a case it
is plain that the enjoyment
does not owe its value
solely to the pleasure it contains, although it might easily have
appeared to do so, when we only considered the other constituents of the
enjoyment, and seemed to see that, without the pleasure, they would have had no
value. It is now apparent, on the contrary, that the whole enjoyment
owes
its value quite equally to the presence of the other constituents, even
though it may be true that the pleasure is the only constituent having any
value by itself. And similarly, if we are told that all things owe their value
solely to the fact that they are realisations of the true self,
we may
easily refute this statement, by asking whether the predicate that is meant by
realising the true self,
supposing that it could exist alone, would have
any value whatsoever. Either the thing, which does realise the true
self,
has intrinsic value or it has not; and if it has, then it certainly
does not owe its value solely to the fact that it realises the true self. (§ 112 ¶ 1)