Chapter III: Hedonism.
§ 55.
The decision,
then, must rest upon Prof.
Sidgwick’s first argument—the appeal
to our intuitive judgment
after due consideration of the question when fairly placed before it.
And
here it seems to me plain that Prof. Sidgwick has failed, in two essential
respects, to place the question fairly before either himself or his reader. (§ 55 ¶ 1)
(1) What he has to shew is, as
he says himself, not merely that Happiness must be included as a part of
Ultimate Good.
This view, he
says, ought not to commend itself to the sober judgment of reflective
persons.
And why? Because these objective relations, when distinguished
from the consciousness accompanying and resulting from them, are not ultimately
and intrinsically desirable.
Now, this reason, which is offered as shewing
that to consider Happiness as a mere part of Ultimate Good does not meet the
facts of intuition, is, on the contrary, only sufficient to shew that it
is a part of Ultimate Good. For from the fact that no value resides in
one part of a whole, considered by itself, we cannot infer that all the value
belonging to the whole does reside in the other part, considered by itself. Even
if we admit that there is much value in the enjoyment of Beauty, and none in the
mere contemplation of it, which is one of the constituents of that complex fact,
it does not follow that all the value belongs to the other constituent, namely,
the pleasure which we take in contemplating it. It is quite possible that this
constituent also has no value in itself; that the value belongs to the whole
state, and to that only: so that both the pleasure and the
contemplation are mere parts of the good, and both of them equally necessary
parts. In short, Prof. Sidgwick’s argument here depends upon the neglect of that
principle, which I tried to explain in my first chapter and which I said I should call the
principle of organic relations.
The argument is calculated to mislead,
because it supposes that, if we see a whole state to be valuable, and also see
that one element of that state has no value by
itself, then the other element, by itself, must have all the value
which belongs to the whole state. The fact is, on the contrary, that, since the
whole may be organic, the other element need have no value whatever, and that
even if it have some, the value of the whole may be very much greater. For this
reason, as well as to avoid confusion between means and end, it is absolutely
essential to consider each distinguishing quality, in isolation, in
order to decide what value it possesses. Prof. Sidgwick, on the other hand,
applies this method of isolation only to one element in the wholes he
is considering. He does not ask the question: If consciousness of pleasure
existed absolutely by itself, would a sober judgment be able to attribute much
value to it? It is, in fact, always misleading to take a whole, that is
valuable (or the reverse), and then to ask simply: To which of its constituents
does this whole owe its value or its vileness? It may well be that it owes it to
none; and, if one of them does appear to have some value in itself, we
shall be led into the grave error of supposing that all the value of the whole
belongs to it alone. It seems to me that this error has commonly been committed
with regard to pleasure. Pleasure does seem to be a necessary constituent of
most valuable wholes; and, since the other constituents, into which we may
analyse them, may easily seem not to have any value, it is natural to suppose
that all the value belongs to pleasure. That this natural supposition does not
follow from the premises is certain; and that it is, on the contrary,
ridiculously far from the truth appears evident to my reflective
judgment.
If we apply either to pleasure or to consciousness of pleasure the
only safe method, that of isolation, and ask ourselves: Could we accept, as a
very good thing, that mere consciousness of pleasure, and absolutely nothing
else, should exist, even in the greatest quantities? I think we can have no
doubt about answering: No. Far less can we accept this as the sole
good. Even if we accept Prof. Sidgwick’s implication (which yet appears to me
extremely doubtful) that consciousness of pleasure has a greater value by itself
than Contemplation of Beauty, it seems to me that a pleasurable Contemplation of
Beauty has certainly an immeasurably greater value than mere Consciousness of
Pleasure. In favour of this conclusion I can appeal with confidence to the
sober judgment of reflective persons.
(§ 55 ¶ 2)
§ 56.
(2) That the
value of a pleasurable whole does not belong solely to the pleasure which it
contains, may, I think, be made still plainer by consideration of another point
in which Prof. Sidgwick’s argument is defective. Prof. Sidgwick maintains, as we
saw, the doubtful proposition, that the conduciveness to pleasure of a
thing is in rough proportion to its commendation by Common Sense. But he does
not maintain, what would be undoubtedly false, that the pleasantness of every
state is in proportion to the commendation of that state. In other words, it is
only when you take into account the whole consequences of any state,
that he is able to maintain the coincidence of quantity of pleasure with the
objects approved by Common Sense. If we consider each state by itself, and ask
what is the judgment of Common Sense as to its goodness as an end,
quite apart from its goodness as a means, there can be no doubt that Common
Sense holds many much less pleasant states to be better than many far more
pleasant: that it holds, with Mill, that there are higher pleasures, which are
more valuable, though less pleasant, than those that are lower. Prof. Sidgwick
might, of course, maintain that in this Common Sense is merely confusing means
and ends: that what it holds to be better as an end, is in reality only better
as a means. But I think his argument is defective in that he does not seem to
see sufficiently plainly that, as far as intuitions of goodness as an
end are concerned, he is running grossly counter to Common Sense; that he
does not emphasise sufficiently the distinction between immediate
pleasantness and conduciveness to pleasure. In order to place fairly
before us the question what is good as an end we must take states that are
immediately pleasant and ask if the more pleasant are always also the better;
and whether, if some that are less pleasant appear to be so, it is only because
we think they are likely to increase the number of the more pleasant. That
Common Sense would deny both these suppositions, and rightly so, appears to me
indubitable. It is commonly held that certain of what would be called the lowest
forms of sexual enjoyment, for instance, are positively bad, although it is by
no means clear that they are not the most pleasant states we ever experience.
Common Sense would certainly not think it a sufficient justification for the
pursuit of what Prof. Sidgwick calls the refined pleasures
here and now,
that they are the best means to the future attainment of a heaven, in which
there would be no more refined pleasures—no contemplation of beauty, no
personal affections—but in which the greatest possible pleasure would be
obtained by a perpetual indulgence in bestiality. Yet Prof. Sidgwick would be
bound to hold that, if the greatest possible pleasure could be obtained in this
way, and if it were attainable, such a state of things would be a heaven indeed,
and that all human endeavours should be devoted to its realisation. I venture to
think that this view is as false as it is paradoxical. (§ 56 ¶ 1)
§ 57.
It seems to
me, then, that if we place fairly before us the question: Is consciousness of
pleasure the sole good? the answer must be: No. And with this the last defence
of Hedonism has been broken down. In order to put the question fairly we must
isolate consciousness of pleasure. We must ask: Suppose we were conscious of
pleasure only, and of nothing else, not even that we were conscious,
would that state of things, however great the quantity, be very desirable? No
one, I think, can suppose it so. On the other hand, it seems quite plain, that
we do regard as very desirable, many complicated states of mind in which the
consciousness of pleasure is combined with consciousness of other things—states
which we call enjoyment of
so and so. If this is correct, then it follows
that consciousness of pleasure is not the sole good, and that many other states,
in which it is included only as a part, are much better than it. Once we
recognise the principle of organic unities, any objection to this conclusion,
founded on the supposed fact that the other elements of such states have no
value in themselves, must disappear. And I do not know that I need say any more
in refutation of Hedonism. (§ 57 ¶ 1)