Chapter VI: The Ideal.
§ 115.
(2) In the last paragraph I have pointed out the two facts, that
the presence of some emotion is necessary to give any very high value to a state
of aesthetic appreciation, and that, on the other hand, this same emotion, in
itself, may have little or no value: it follows that these emotions give to the
wholes of which they form a part a value far greater than that which they
themselves possess. The same is obviously true of the cognitive element which
must be combined with these emotions in order to form these highly valuable
wholes; and the present paragraph will attempt to define what is meant by this
cognitive element, so far as to guard against a possible misunderstanding. When
we talk of seeing a beautiful object, or, more generally, of the cognition or
consciousness of a beautiful object, we may mean by these expressions something
which forms no part of any valuable whole. There is an ambiguity in the use of
the term object,
which has probably been responsible for as many enormous
errors in philosophy and psychology as any other single cause. This ambiguity
may easily be detected by considering the proposition, which, though a
contradiction in terms, is obviously true: That when a man sees a beautiful
picture, he may see nothing beautiful whatever. The ambiguity consists in the
fact that, by the object
of vision (or cognition), may be meant
either the qualities actually seen or all the qualities possessed by
the thing seen. Thus in our case: when it is said that the picture is beautiful,
it is meant that it contains qualities which are beautiful; when it is said that
the man sees the picture, it is meant that he sees a great number of the
qualities contained in the picture; and when it is said that, nevertheless, he
sees nothing beautiful, it is meant that he does not see those
qualities of the picture which are beautiful. When, therefore, I speak of the
cognition of a beautiful object, as an essential element in a valuable aesthetic
appreciation, I must be understood to mean only the cognition of the
beautiful qualities possessed by that object, and not the
cognition of other qualities of the object possessing them. And this distinction
must itself be carefully distinguished from the other distinction expressed
above by the distinct terms seeing the beauty of a thing
and seeing
its beautiful qualities.
By seeing the beauty of a thing
we commonly
mean the having an emotion towards its beautiful qualities; whereas in the
seeing of its beautiful qualities
we do not include any emotion. By the
cognitive element, which is equally necessary with emotions to the existence of
a valuable appreciation, I mean merely the actual cognition or consciousness of
any or all of an object’s beautiful qualities—that is to
say, any or all of those elements in the object which possess any positive
beauty. That such a cognitive element is essential to a valuable whole may be
easily seen, by asking: What value should we attribute to the proper emotion
excited by hearing Beethoven’s Fifth Symphony, if that emotion were
entirely unaccompanied by any consciousness, either of the notes, or of the
melodic and harmonic relations between them? And that the mere hearing
of the Symphony, even accompanied by the appropriate emotion, is not sufficient,
may be easily seen, if we consider what would be the state of a man, who should
hear all the notes, but should not be aware of any of those melodic and
harmonic relations, which are necessary to constitute the smallest beautiful
elements in the Symphony. (§ 115 ¶ 1)