Chapter VI: The Ideal.
§ 116.
(3) Connected with the distinction just made between object
in the sense
of the qualities actually before the mind and object
in the sense of the
whole thing which possesses the qualities actually before the mind, is another
distinction of the utmost importance for a correct analysis of the constituents
necessary to a valuable whole. It is commonly and rightly thought that to see
beauty in a thing which has no beauty is in some way inferior to seeing beauty
in that which really has it. But under this single description of seeing
beauty in that which has no beauty,
two very different facts, and facts of
very different value, may be included. We may mean either the
attribution to an object of really beautiful qualities which it does not possess
or the feeling towards qualities, which the object does possess but
which are in reality not beautiful, an emotion which is appropriate only to
qualities really beautiful. Both these facts are of very frequent occurrence;
and in most instances of emotion both no doubt occur together: but they are
obviously quite distinct, and the distinction is of the utmost importance for a
correct estimate of values. The former may be called an error of judgment, and
the latter an error of taste; but it is important to observe that the error
of taste
commonly involves a false judgment of value; whereas the
error of judgment
is merely a false judgment of fact. (§ 116 ¶ 1)
Now the case which I have called an error of taste, namely, where the actual
qualities we admire (whether possessed by the object
or not) are ugly,
can in any case have no value, except such as may belong to the emotion by
itself; and in most, if not in all, cases it is a considerable positive
evil. In this sense, then, it is undoubtedly right to think that seeing beauty
in a thing which has no beauty is inferior in value to seeing beauty where
beauty really is. But the other case is much more difficult. In this case there
is present all that I have hitherto mentioned as necessary to constitute a great
positive good: there is a cognition of qualities really beautiful, together with
an appropriate emotion towards these qualities. There can, therefore, be no
doubt that we have here a great positive good. But there is present also
something else; namely, a belief that these beautiful qualities exist, and that
they exist in a certain relation to other things—namely, to some properties of
the object to which we attribute these qualities: and further the object of this
belief is false. And we may ask, with regard to the whole thus constituted,
whether the presence of the belief, and the fact that what is believed is false,
make any difference to its value? We thus get three different cases of which it
is very important to determine the relative values. Where both the cognition of
beautiful qualities and the appropriate emotion are present we may also have
either (1) a belief in the existence of these qualities, of which the object,
i.e. that they exist, is
true: or (2) a mere cognition, without belief, when it is (a) true, (b)
false, that the object of the cognition, i.e. the beautiful qualities, exists: or (3) a
belief in the existence of the beautiful qualities, when they do not exist. The
importance of these cases arises from the fact that the second defines the
pleasures of imagination, including a great part of the appreciation of those
works of art which are representative; whereas the first contrasts with these
the appreciation of what is beautiful in Nature, and the human affections. The
third, on the other hand, is contrasted with both, in that it is chiefly
exemplified in what is called misdirected affection; and it is possible also
that the love of God, in the case of a believer, should fall under this head. (§ 116 ¶ 2)