Chapter IV: Metaphysical Ethics.
§ 75.
The fallacy of
supposing moral law to be analogous to natural law in respect of asserting that
some action is one which is always necessarily done is contained in one of the
most famous doctrines of Kant. Kant identifies what ought to be with the law
according to which a Free or Pure Will must act—with the only kind of
action which is possible for it. And by this identification he does not mean
merely to assert that Free Will is also under the necessity of doing
what it ought; he means that what it ought to do means nothing but its
own law—the law according to which it must act. It differs from the human will
just in that, what we ought to do, is what it necessarily
does. It is autonomous
; and by this is meant (among other things) that
there is no separate standard by which it can be judged: that the question Is
the law by which this Will acts a good one?
is, in its case, meaningless. It
follows that what is necessarily willed by this Pure Will is good, not
because that Will is good, nor for any other reason; but merely because
it is what is necessarily willed by a Pure Will. (§ 75 ¶ 1)
Kant's assertion of the Autonomy of the Practical Reason
thus has the very opposite effect to that which he desired; it makes his Ethics
ultimately and hopelessly heteronomous.
His Moral Law is
independent
of Metaphysics only in the sense that according to him we can
knnow it independently; he holds that we can only infer that there is
Freedom, from the fact that the Moral Law is true. And so far as he keeps
strictly to this view, he does avoid the error, into which most metaphysical
writers fall, of allowing his opinions as to what is real to influence his
judgments of what is good. But he fails to see that on his view the Moral Law is
dependent upon Freedom in a far more important sense than that in which Freedom
depends on the Moral Law. He admits that Freedom is the ratio essendi of the Moral Law, whereas the latter is only
the ratio cognoscendi of Freedom. And this means
that, unless Reality be such as he says, no assertion that This is good
can possibly be true: it can indeed have no meaning. He has, therefore,
furnished his opponents with a conclusive method of attacking the validity of
the Moral Law. If they can only shew by some other means (which he denies to be
possible but leaves theoretically open) that the nature of Reality is not such
as he says, he cannot deny that they will have proved his ethical principle to
be false. If what This ought be done
means This is willed by
a Free Will,
then, if it can be shewn that there is no Free Will which wills
anything, it will follow that nothing ought to be done. (§ 75 ¶ 2)