Chapter I: The Subject-Matter of Ethics.
§ 18.
There remains
one point which must not be ommitted in a complete description of the kind of
questions which Ethics has to answer. The main division of these questions is,
as I have said, into two; the question what things are good in themselves, and
the question to what other things these are related as effects. The first of
these, which is the primary ethical question and is presupposed by the other,
includes a correct comparison of the various things which have intrinsic value
(if there are many such) in respect of the degree of value which they have; and
such comparison involves a difficulty of principle which has greatly aided the
confusion of intrinsic value with mere goodness as a means.
It has been
pointed out that one difference between a judgment which asserts that a thing is
good in itself, and a judgment which asserts that it is a means to good,
consists in the fact that the first, if true of one instance of the thing in
question, is necessarily true of all; whereas a thing which has good effects
under some circumstances may have bad ones under others. Now it is certainly
true that all judgments of intrinsic value are in this sense universal; but the
principle which I have now to enunciate may easily make it appear as if they
were not so but resembled the judgment of means in being merely general. There
is, as will presently be maintained, a vast number of different things, each of
which has intrinsic value; there are also very many which are positively bad;
and there is a still larger class of things, which appear to be indifferent. But
a thing belonging to any of these three classes may occur as part of a whole,
which includes among its other parts other things belonging both to the same and
to the other two classes; and these wholes, as such, may also have intrinsic
value. The paradox, to which it is necessary to call attention, is that the
value of such a whole bears no regular proportion to the sum of the values of
its parts. It is certain that a good thing may exist in such a relation to
another good thing that the value of the whole thus formed is immensely greater
than the sum of the values of the two good things. It is certain that a whole
formed of a good thing and an indifferent thing may have immensely greater value
than that good thing itself possesses. It is certain that two bad things or a
bad thing and an indifferent thing may form a whole much worse than the sum of
badness of its parts. And it seems as if indifferent things may also be the sole
constituents of a whole which has great value, either positive or negative.
Whether the addition of a bad thing to a good whole may increase the positive
value of the whole, or the addition of a bad thing to a bad may produce a whole
having a positive value, may seem more doubtful; but it is, at least, possible,
and this possibility must be taken into account in our ethical investigations.
However we may decide particular questions, the principle is clear. The
value of a whole must not be assumed to be the same as the sum of the values of
its parts. (§ 18 ¶ 1)
A single instance will suffice to illustrate the kind of relation in question. It seems to be true that to be conscious of a beautiful object is of great intrinsic value; whereas the same object, if no one be conscious of it, has certainly comparatively little value, and it is commonly held to have none at all. But the consciousness of a beautiful object is certainly a whole of some sort in which we can distinguish as parts the object on the one hand and the being conscious on the other. Now this latter factor occurs as part of a different whole, whenever we are conscious of anything; and it would seem that some of these wholes have at all events very little value, and may even be indifferent or positively bad. Yet we cannot always attribute the slightness of their value to any positive demerit in the object which differentiates them from the consciousness of beauty; the object itself may approach as near as possible to absolute neutrality. Since, therefore, mere consciousness does not always confer great value upon the whole of which it forms a part, we cannot attribute the great superiority of the consciousness of a beautiful thing over the beautiful thing itself to the mere addition of the value of consciousness to that of the beautiful thing. Whatever the intrinsic value of consciousness may be, it does not give to the whole of which it forms a part a value proportional to the sum of its value and that of its object. If this be so, we have here an instance of a whole possessing a different intrinsic value from the sum of that of its parts; and whether it be so or not, what is meant by such a difference is illustrated by this case. (§ 18 ¶ 2)
§ 19.
There are, then, wholes which possess the property that their value is different from the sum of the values of their parts, and the relations which subsist between such parts and the whole of which they form a part have not hitherto been distinctly recognised or received a separate name. Two points are especially worthy of notice. (1) It is plain that the existence of any such part is a necessary condition for the existence of that good which is constituted by the whole. And exactly the same language will also express the relation between a means and the good thing which is its effect. But yet there is a most important difference between the two cases, constituted by the fact that the part is, whereas the means is not, a part of the good thing for the existence of which its existence is a necessary condition. The necessity by which, if the good in question is to exist, the means to it must exist is merely a natural or causal necessity. If the laws of nature were different, exactly the same good might exist, although what is now a necessary condition of its existence did not exist. The existence of the means has no intrinsic value; and its utter annihilation would leave the value of that which it is now necessary to secure entirely unchanged. But in the case of a part of such a whole as we are now considering, it is otherwise. In this case the good in question cannot conceivably exist, unless the part exist also. The necessity which connects the two is quite independent of natural law. What is asserted to have intrinsic value is the existence of the whole; and the existence of the whole includes the existence of its part. Suppose the part removed, and what remains is not what was asserted to have intrinsic value; but if we suppose a means removed, what remains is just what was asserted to have intrinsic value. And yet (2) the existence of the part may itself have no more intrinsic value than that of the means. It is this fact which constitutes the paradox of the relation which we are discussing. It has just been said that what has intrinsic value is the existence of the whole, and that this includes the existence of the part; and from this it would seem a natural inference that the existence of the part has intrinsic value. But the inference would be as false as if we were to conclude that, because the number of two stones was two, each of the stones was also two. The part of a valuable whole retains exactly the same value when it is, as when it is not, a part of that whole. If it had value under other circumstances, its value is not any greater, when it is part of a far more valuable whole; and if it had no value by itself, it has none still, however great be that of the whole of which it now forms a part. We are not then justified in asserting that one and the same thing is under some circumstances intrinsically good, and under others not so; as we are justified in asserting of a means that it sometimes does and sometimes does not produce good results. And yet we are justified in asserting that it is far more desirable that a certain thing should exist under some circumstances than under others; namely when other things will exist in such relations to it as to form a more valuable whole. It will not have more intrinsic value under those circumstances than under others; it will not necessarily even be a means to the existence of things having more intrinsic value; but it will, like a means, be a necessary condition for the existence of that which has greater intrinsic value, although, unlike a means, it will itself form a part of the more valuable existent. (§ 19 ¶ 1)
§ 20.
I have said that
the peculiar relation between part and whole which I have just been trying to
define is one which has received no separate name. It would, however, be useful
that it should have one; and there is a name, which might well be appropriated
to it, if only it could be divorced from its present unfortunate usage.
Philosophers, especially those who profess to have derived great benefit from
the writings of Hegel, have latterly made much use of the terms organic
whole,
organic unity,
organic relation.
The reason why these
terms might well be appropriated to the use suggested is that the peculiar
relation of parts to whole, just defined, is one of the properties which
distinguishes the wholes to which they are actually applied with the greatest
frequency. And the reason why it is desirable that they should be divorced from
their present usage is that, as at present used, they have no distinct sense
and, on the contrary, both imply and propagate errors of confusion. (§ 20 ¶ 1)
To say that a thing is an organic whole
is generally
understood to imply that its parts are related to one another and to itself as
means to end; it is also understood to imply that they have a property described
in some such phrase as that they have no meaning or significance apart from
the whole
; and finally such a whole is also treated as if it had the
property to which I am proposing that the name should be confined. But those who
use the term give us, in general, no hint as to how they suppose these three
properties to be related to one another. It seems generally to be assumed that
they are identical; and always, at least, that they are necessarily connected
with one another. That they are not identical I have already tried to shew; to
suppose them so is to neglect the very distinctions pointed out in the last
paragraph; and the usage might well be discontinued merely because it encourages
such neglect. But a still more cogent reason for its discontinuance is that, so
far from being necessarily connected, the second is a property which can attach
to nothing, being a self-contradictory conception; whereas the first, if we
insist on its most important sense, applies to many cases, to which we have no
reason to think that the third applies also, and the third certainly applies to
many to which the first does not apply. (§ 20 ¶ 2)
§ 21.
These relations
between the three properties just distinguished may be illustrated by references
to a whole of the kind from which the name organic
was derived—a whole
which is an organism in the scientific sense—namely the human body. (§ 21 ¶ 1)
(1) There exists between many parts of our body (though not
between all) a relation which has been familiarised by the
fable, attributed to Menenius Agrippa, concerning the belly and its members.
We can find it in parts such that the continued existence of one is a necessary
condition for the continued existence of the other; while the continued
existence of this latter is also a necessary condition for the continued
existence of the former. This amounts to no more than saying that in the body we
hve instances of two things, both enduring for some time, which have a relation
of mutual causal dependence on one another—a relation of
reciprocity.
Frequently no more than this is meant by saying that the
parts of the body form an organic unity,
or that they are mutually means
and ends to one another. And we certainly have here a striking characteristic of
living things. But it would be extremely rash to assert that this relation of
mutual causal dependence was only exhibited by living things and hence was
sufficient to define their peculiarity. And it is obvious that of two things
which have this relation of mutual dependence, neither may have intrinsic value,
or one may have it and the other lack it. They are not necessarily ends
to one another in any sense except that in which end
means effect.
And moreover it is plain that in this sense the whole cannot be an end to any of
its parts. We are apt to talk of the whole
in contrast to one of its
parts, when in fact we mean only the rest of the parts. But strictly
the whole must include all its parts and no part can be a cause of the whole,
because it cannot be a cause of itself. It is plain, therefore, that this
relation of mutual causal dependence implies nothing with regard to the value of
either of the objects which have it; and that, even if both of them happen also
to have value, this relation between them is one which cannot hold between part
and whole. (§ 21 ¶ 2)
But (2) it may also be the case that our body as a whole has a
value greater than the sum of values of its parts; and this may be what is meant
when it is said that the parts are means to the whole. It is obvious that if we
ask the question Why should the parts be such as they are?
a
proper answer may be Because the whole they form has so much value.
But
it is equally obvious that the relation which we thus assert to exist between
part and whole is quite different from that which we assert to exist between
part and part when we say This part exists, because that one could not exist
without it.
In the latter case we assert the two parts to be causally
connected; but, in the former, part and whole cannot be causally connected and
the relation which we assert to exist between them may exist even though the
parts are not causally connected either. All the parts of a picture do not have
that relation of mutual causal dependence, which certain parts of the body have,
and yet the existence of those which do not have it may be absolutely essential
to the value of the whole. The two relations are quite distinct in kind, and we
cannot infer the existence of the one from that of the other. It can, therefore,
serve no useful purpose to include them both under the same name; and if we are
to say that a whole is organic because its parts are (in this sense)
means
to the whole, we must not say that it is organic because
its parts are causally dependent on one another. (§ 21 ¶ 3)
§ 22.
But finally (3)
the sense which has been most prominent in recent uses of the term organic
whole
is one whereby it asserts the parts of such a whole have a property
which the parts of no whole can possibly have. It is supposed that just as the
whole would not be what it is but for the existence of the parts, so the parts
would not be what they are but for the existence of the whole; and this is
understood to mean not merely that any particular part could not exist unless
the others existed too (which is the case where relation (1) exists
between the parts), but actually that the part is no distinct
object of thought—that the whole, of which it is a part, is in turn a part of
it. That this supposition is self-contradictory a very little reflection should
be sufficient to shew. We may admit, indeed, that when a particular thing is a
part of a whole, it does possess a predicate which it would not otherwise
possess—namely that it is a part of the whole. But what cannot be admitted is
that this predicate alters the nature or enters into the definition of the thing
which has it. When we think of the part itself, we mean just that
which we assert, in this case, to have the predicate that it is
part of the whole; and the mere assertion that it is a part of the
whole involves that it should itself be distinct from that which we assert of
it. Otherwise we contradict ourselves since we assert that, not it, but
something else—namely it together with that which we assert of it—has the
predicate which we assert of it. In short, it is obvious that no part contains
analytically the whole to which it belongs, or any other parts of that whole.
The relation of part to whole is not the same as that of whole to part;
and the very definition of the latter is that it does contain analytically that
which it is said to be its part. And yet this very self-contradictory doctrine
is the chief mark which shews the influence of Hegel upon modern philosophy—an
influence which pervades almost the whole of orthodox philosophy. This is what
is generally implied by the cry against falsification by abstraction: that a
whole is always a part of its part! If you want to know the truth about a
part,
we are told, you must consider not that part, but
something else—namely the whole: nothing is true of the part, but only
of the whole.
Yet plainly it must be true of the part at least that it is
part of the whole; and it is obvious that when we say it is, we do not
mean merely that the whole is a part of itself. This doctrine, therefore, that a
part can have no meaning or significance apart from its whole
must be
utterly rejected. It implies itself that the statement This is a part of that
whole
has a meaning; and in order that this may have one, both subject and
predicate must have a distinct meaning. And it is easy to see how this flse
doctrine has arisen by confusion with the two relations (1) and (2)
which may really be properties of wholes. (§ 22 ¶ 1)
(a) The existence of a part may be connected by
a natural or causal necessity with the existence of the other parts of its
whole; and further what is a part of a whole and what has ceased to be such a
part, although differing intrinsically from one another, may be called by one
and the same name. Thus, to take a typical example, if an arm be cut off from
the human body, we still call it an arm. Yet an arm, when it is a part of the
body, undoubtedly differs from a dead arm; and hence we may easily be led to say
The arm which is a part of the body would not be what it is, if it were not
such a part,
and to think that the contradiction thus expressed is in
reality a characteristic of things. But, in fact, the dead arm never was a part
of the body; it is only partially identical with the living arm. Those
parts of it which are identical with parts of the living arm are exactly the
same, whether they belong to the body or not; and in them we have an undeniable
instance of one and the same thing at one time forming a part, and at another
not forming a part of the presumed organic whole.
On the other hand those
properties which are possessed by the living, and not by the dead arm,
do not exist in a changed form in the latter: they simply do not exist there
at all. By a causal necessity their existence depends on their having
that relation to the other parts of the body which we express by saying that
they form part of it. Yet, most certainly, if they ever did not form
part of the body, they would be exactly what they are when they do.
That they differ intrinsically from the properties of the dead arm and that they
form part of the body are propositions not analytically related to one another.
There is no contradiction in supposing them to retain such intrinsic differences
and yet not to form part of the body. (§ 22 ¶ 2)
But (b) when we are told that a living arm has no
meaning or significance apart from the body to which it
belongs, a different fallacy is also suggested. To have meaning or
significance
is commonly used in the sense of to have importance
; and
this again means to have value either as a means or as an end.
Now it is
quite possible that even a living arm, apart from its body, would have no
intrinsic value whatever; although the whole of which it is a part has great
intrinsic value owing to its presence. Thus we may easily come to say that,
as a part of the body, it has great value, whereas by itself
it would have none; and thus that its whole meaning
lies in its relation
to the body. But in fact the value in question obviously does not belong to
it at all. To have value merely as a part is equivalent to having no
value at all, but merely being a part of that which has it. Owing, however, to
neglect of this distinction, the assertion that a part has value, as a
part, which it would not otherwise have, easily leads to the assumption
that it is also different, as a part, from what it would otherwise be; for it
is, in fact, true that two things which have a different value must also differ
in other respects. Hence the assumption that one and the same thing, because it
is a part of a more valuable whole at one time than at another, therefore has
more intrinsic value at one time than at another, has encouraged the
self-contradictory belief that one and the same thing may be two different
things, and that only in one of its forms is it truly what it is.
(§ 22 ¶ 3)
For these reasons, I shall, where it seems convenient, take the
liberty to use the term organic
with a special sense. I shall use it to
denote the fact that a whole has an intrinsic value different in amount from the
sum of the values of its parts. I shall use it to denote this and only this. The
term will not imply any causal relation whatever between the parts of the whole
in question. And it will not imply either, that the parts are inconceivable
except as parts of that whole, or that, when they form parts of such a whole,
they have a value different from that which they would have if they did not.
Understood in this special and perfectly definite sense the relation of an
organic whole to its parts is one of the most important which Ethics has to
recognise. A chief part of that science should be occupied in comparing the
relative values of various goods; and the grossest errors will be committed in
such comparison if it be assumed that wherever two things form a whole, the
value of that whole is merely the sum of the values of those two things. With
this question of organic wholes,
then, we complete the enumeration of the
kind of problems, with which it is the business of Ethics to deal.
(§ 22 ¶ 4)