Chapter II: Naturalistic Ethics.
§ 32.
Whatever be
the degree of Mr Spencer’s own guilt, what has
just been said will serve to illustrate the kind of fallacy which is constantly
committed by those who profess to base
Ethics on Evolution. But we must
hasten to add that the view which Mr Spencer
elsewhere most emphatically recommends is an utterly different one. It will be
useful briefly to deal with this, in order that no injustice may be done to
Mr Spencer. The discussion will be instructive
partly from the lack of clearness, which Mr Spencer
displays, as to the relation of this view to the evolutionistic
one just
described; and partly because there is reason to suspect that in this view also
he is influenced by the naturalistic fallacy. (§ 32 ¶ 1)
We have seen that, at the end of his second chapter, Mr Spencer seems to announce that he has already proved
certain characteristics of conduct to be a measure of its ethical value. He
seems to think that he has proved this merely by considering the evolution of
conduct; and he has certainly not given any such proof, unless we are to
understand that more evolved
is a mere synonym for ethically
better.
He now promises merely to confirm this certain conclusion
by shewing that it harmonizes with the leading moral ideas men have otherwise
reached.
But, when we turn to his third chapter, we find that what he
actually does is something quite different. He here asserts that to establish
the conclusion Conduct is better in proportion as it is more evolved
an
entirely new proof is necessary. That conclusion will be false, unless
a certain proposition, of which we have heard nothing so far, is
true—unless it is true that life is pleasant on the whole. And
the ethical proposition, for which he claims the support of the leading moral
ideas
of mankind, turns out to be that life is good
or bad, according as it does, or does not, bring a surplus of agreeable
feeling
(§ 10).
Here, then, Mr Spencer appears, not as an
Evolutionist, but as a Hedonist, in Ethics. No conduct is better,
because it is more evolved. Degree of evolution can at most be a
criterion of ethical value; and it will only be that, if we can prove
the extremely difficult generalisation that the more evolved is always, on the
whole, the pleasanter. It is plain that Mr Spencer
here rejects the naturalistic identification of better
with more
evolved
; but it is possible that he is influenced by another naturalistic
identification—that of good
with pleasant.
It is possible
that Mr Spencer is a naturalistic Hedonist. (§ 32 ¶ 2)
§ 33.
Let us examine
Mr Spencer’s own words. He begins this third
chapter by an attempt to
shew that we call good the acts conducive to life, in
self or others, and bad those which directly or indirectly tend towards death,
special or general
(§ 9).
And then he
asks: Is there any
assumption made
in so calling them? Yes
; he
answers, an
assumption of extreme significance has been made—an assumption underlying
all moral estimates. The question to be definitely raised and answered before
entering on any ethical discussion, is the question of late much
agitated—Is life worth living? Shall we take the pessimist view? or shall
we take the optimist view?… On the answer to this question depends every
decision concerning the goodness or badness of conduct.
But Mr Spencer does not immediately proceed to give the
answer. Instead of this, he asks
another question: But now, have
these irreconcilable opinions [pessimist and optimist] anything in common?
And this question he
immediately answers by the statement: Yes, there is one postulate in
which pessimists and optimists agree. Both their arguments assume it to be
self-evident that life is good or bad, according as it does, or does not, bring
a surplus of agreeable feeling
(§ 10).
It is to the defence of this statement that the rest of the chapter is devoted;
and at the end Mr Spencer formulates his conclusion
in the following words: No school
can avoid taking for the ultimate moral aim a desirable state of feeling called
by whatever name—gratification, enjoyment, happiness. Pleasure somewhere,
at some time, to some being or beings, is an inexpugnable element of the
conception
(§ 16
ad fin.). (§ 33 ¶ 1)
Now in all this, there are two points to which I wish to call
attention. The first is that Mr Spencer does not,
after all, tell us clearly what he takes to be the relation of Pleasure and
Evolution in ethical theory. Obviously he should mean that pleasure is the
only intrinsically desirable thing; that other good things are
good
only in the sense that they are means to its existence. Nothing but
this can properly be meant by asserting it to be the ultimate moral
aim,
or, as he
subsequently says (§ 62ad fin.),
the
ultimately supreme end.
And, if this were so, it would follow that the more
evolved conduct was better than the less evolved, only because, and in
proportion as, it gave more pleasure. But Mr Spencer
tells us that two conditions are, taken together, sufficient to prove
the more evolved conduct better: (1) That it should tend to produce more life;
(2) That life should be worth living or contain a balance of pleasure. And the
point I wish to emphasise is that if these conditions are sufficient, then
pleasure cannot be the sole good. For though to produce more life is, if the
second of Mr Spencer’s propositions be
correct, one way of producing more pleasure, it is not the only way. It
is quite possible that a small quantity of life, which was more intensely and
uniformly present, should give a greater quantity of pleasure than the greatest
possible quantity of life that was only just worth living.
And in that
case, on the hedonistic supposition that pleasure is the only thing worth
having, we should have to prefer the smaller quantity of life and therefore,
according to Mr Spencer, the less evolved conduct.
Accordingly, if Mr Spencer is a true Hedonist, the
fact that life gives a balance of pleasure is not, as he seems to
think, sufficient to prove that the more evolved conduct is the better. If Mr Spencer means us to understand that it is
sufficient, then his view about pleasure can only be, not that it is the sole
good or ultimately supreme end,
but that a balance of it is a necessary
constituent of the supreme end. In short, Mr Spencer
seems to maintain that more life is decidedly better than less, if only
it give a balance of pleasure: and that contention is inconsistent with the
position that pleasure is the ultimate moral aim.
Mr Spencer implies that of two quantities of life, which
gave an equal amount of pleasure, the larger would nevertheless be preferable to
the less. And if this be so, then he must maintain that quantity of life or
degree of evolution is itself an ultimate condition of value. He leaves us,
therefore, in doubt whether he is not still retaining the Evolutionistic
proposition, that the more evolved is better, simply because it is more evolved,
alongside the Hedonistic proposition, that the more pleasant is better, simply
because it is more pleasant. (§ 33 ¶ 2)
But the second question which we have to ask is: What reasons has
Mr Spencer for assigning to pleasure the position
which he does assign to it? He tells
us, we saw, that the arguments
both of pessimists and of optimists assume it
to be self-evident that life is good or bad, according as it does, or does not,
bring a surplus of agreeable feeling
; and he betters this later by telling
us that since
avowed or implied pessimists, and optimists of one or other shade, taken
together constitute all men, it results that this postulate is universally
accepted
(§ 16).
That these statements are absolutely false is, of course, quite obvious: but why
does Mr Spencer think them true? and, what is more
important (a question which Mr Spencer does not
distinguish too clearly from the last), why does he think the postulate itself
to be true? Mr Spencer himself tells us his proof
is
that reversing
the application of the words
good and bad—applying the word
good
to conduct, the aggregate
results
of which are painful, and the word bad
to conduct, of which
the aggregate
results
are pleasurable—creates
absurdities
(§ 16). He
does not say whether this is because it is absurd to think that the quality,
which we mean by the word good,
really applies to what is
painful. Even, however, if we assume him to mean this, and if we assume that
absurdities are thus created, it is plain he would only prove that what is
painful is properly thought to be so far bad, and what is pleasant to
be so far good: it would not prove at all that pleasure is
the supreme end.
There is, however, reason to think that part of
what Mr Spencer means is the naturalistic fallacy:
that he imagines pleasant
or productive of pleasure
is the very
meaning of the word good,
and that the absurdity
is due to this.
It is at all events certain that he does not distinguish this possible meaning
from that which would admit that good
denotes an unique indefinable
quality. The doctrine of naturalistic Hedonism is, indeed, quite strictly
implied in his statement that virtue
cannot be
defined otherwise than in terms of happiness
(§ 13);
and, though, as I remarked above, we cannot insist upon Mr Spencer’s words as a certain clue to any definite
meaning, that is only because he generally expresses by them several
inconsistent alternatives—the naturalistic fallacy being, in this case,
one such alternative. It is certainly impossible to find any further reasons
given by Mr Spencer for his conviction that pleasure
both is the supreme end, and is universally admitted to be so. He seems to
assume throughout that we must mean by good conduct what is productive
of pleasure, and by bad what is productive of pain. So far, then, as he is a
Hedonist, he would seem to be a naturalistic Hedonist. (§ 33 ¶ 3)
So much for Mr Spencer. It is, of
course, quite possible that his treatment of Ethics contains many interesting
and instructive remarks. It would seem, indeed, that Mr Spencer’s main view, that of which he is most
clearly and most often conscious, is that pleasure is the sole good, and that to
consider the direction of evolution is by far the best criterion of the
way in which we shall get most of it; and this theory, if he could
establish that amount of pleasure is always in direct proportion to amount of
evolution and also that it was plain what conduct was more evolved,
would be a very valuable contribution to the science of Sociology; it
would even, if pleasure were the sole good, be a valuable contribution to
Ethics. But the above discussion should have made it plain that, if what we want
from an ethical philosopher is a scientific and systematic Ethics, not merely an
Ethics professedly based on science
; if what we want is a clear
discussion of the fundamental principles of Ethics, and a statement of the
ultimate reasons why one way of acting should be considered better than
another—then Mr Spencer’s Data
of Ethics is immeasurably far from satisfying these demands.
(§ 33 ¶ 4)