Chapter III: Hedonism.
§ 46.
Well, then, we
now proceed to discuss Intuitionistic Hedonism. And the beginning of this
discussion marks, it is to be observed, a turning-point in my ethical method.
The point I have been labouring hitherto, the point that good is
indefinable,
and that to deny this involves a fallacy, is a point capable of
strict proof: for to deny it involves contradictions. But now we are coming to
the question, for the sake of answering which Ethics exists, the question what
things or qualities are good. Of any answer to this question no direct
proof is possible, and that, just because of our former answer, as to the
meaning of good, direct proof was possible. We are now confined to the
hope of what Mill calls indirect proof,
the hope of determining one
another’s intellect; and we are now so confined, just because, in the matter of
the former question we are not so confined. Here, then, is an intuition to be
submitted to our verdict—the intuition that pleasure alone is good as an
end—good in and for itself.
(§ 46 ¶ 1)
§ 47.
Well, in
this connection, it seems first desirable to touch on another doctrine of
Mill’s—another doctrine which, in the interest of Hedonism,
Professor Sidgwick has done very wisely to reject. This is the doctrine of
difference of quality in pleasures.
If I am asked,
says Mill, what I mean
by difference of quality in pleasures, or what makes one pleasure more valuable
than another, merely as a pleasure, except its being greater in amount, there is
but one possible answer. Of two pleasures, if there be one to which all or
almost all who have experience of both give a decided preference, irrespective
of any feeling of moral obligation to prefer it, that is the more desirable
pleasure. If one of the two is, by those who are competantly acquainted with
both, placed so far above the other that they prefer it, even though knowing it
to be attended with a greater amount of discontent, and would not resign it for
any quantity of the other pleasure which their nature is capable of, we are
justified in ascribing to the preferred enjoyment a superiority in quality, so
far outweighing quantity as to render it, in comparison, of small account.
(§ 47 ¶ 1)
Now it is well known that Bentham rested his case for Hedonism on
quantity of pleasure
alone. It was his maxim, that quantity of
pleasure being equal, pushpin is as good as poetry.
And Mill apparently
considers Bentham to have proved that nevertheless poetry is better than
pushpin; that poetry does produce a greater quantity of pleasure. But yet,
says
Mill, the Utilitarians might have taken the other and, as it may
be called, higher ground, with entire consistency
(p.
11). Now we see from this that Mill acknowledges quality of pleasure
to be another or different ground for estimating pleasures, than Bentham’s
quantity; and moreover, by that question-begging higher,
which he
afterwards translates into superior,
he seems to betray an uncomfortable
feeling, that, after all, if you take quantity of pleasure for your only
standard, something may be wrong and you may deserve to be called a pig. And it
may presently appear that you very likely would deserve this name. But,
meanwhile, I only wish to shew that Mill’s admissions as to the quality of
pleasure are either inconsistent with his Hedonism, or else afford no other
ground for it than would be given by mere quantity of pleasure. (§ 47 ¶ 2)
It will be seen that Mill’s test for one pleasure’s superiority in
quality over another is the preference of most people who have experienced both.
A pleasure so preferred, he holds, is more desirable. But then, as we have
seen, he
holds that to think of an object as desirable and to think of it as
pleasant are one and the same thing
(p.
58). He holds,
therefore, that the preference of experts merely proves that one pleasure is
pleasanter than another. But if that is so, how can he distinguish this standard
from the standard of quantity of pleasure? Can one pleasure be pleasanter than
another, except in the sense that it gives more pleasure?
Pleasant
must, if words are to have any meaning at all, denote some one
quality common to all things that are pleasant; and, if so, then one thing can
only be more pleasant than another, according as it has more or less of this one
quality. But, then, let us try the other alternative, and suppose that Mill does
not seriously mean that this preference of experts merely proves one pleasure to
be pleasanter than another. Well, in this case, what does preferred
mean?
It cannot mean more desired,
since, as we know, the degree of desire is
always, according to Mill, in exact proportion to the degree of pleasantness.
But, in that case, the basis of Mill’s Hedonism collapses, for he is admitting
that one thing may be preferred over another, and thus proved more desirable,
although it is not more desired. In this case, Mill’s judgment of preference is
just a judgment of that intuitional kind which I have been contending to be
necessary to establish the hedonistic or any other principle. It is a direct
judgment that one thing is more desirable, or better than another; a judgment
utterly independent of all considerations as to whether one thing is more
desired or pleasanter than another. This is to admit that good is good and
indefinable. (§ 47 ¶ 3)
§ 48.
And note
another point that is brought out by this discussion. Mill’s judgment of
preference, so far from establishing the principle that pleasure alone is good,
is obviously inconsistent with it. He admits that experts can judge whether one
pleasure is more desirable than another, because pleasures differ in quality.
But what does this mean? If one pleasure can differ from another in quality,
that means, that a pleasure is something complex, something composed,
in fact, of pleasure in addition to that which produces pleasure. For
instance, Mill speaks of sensual indulgences
as lower pleasures.
But what is a sensual indulgence? It is surely a certain excitement of some
sense together with the pleasure caused by such excitement. Mill,
therefore, in admitting that a sensual indulgence can be directly judged to be
lower than another pleasure, in which the degree of pleasure involved may be the
same, is admitting that other things may be good, or bad, quite independently of
the pleasure which accompanies them. A pleasure is, in fact, merely a
misleading term which conceals the fact that what we are dealing with is not
pleasure but something else, which may indeed necessarily produce pleasure, but
is nevertheless quite distinct from it. (§ 48 ¶ 1)
Mill, therefore, in thinking that to estimate quality of pleasure is quite consistent with his hedonistic principle that pleasure and absence of pain alone are desirable as ends has again committed the fallacy of confusing ends and means. For take even the most favourable supposition of his meaning; let us suppose that by a pleasure he does not mean, as his words imply, that which produces pleasure and the pleasure produced. Let us suppose him to mean that there are various kinds of pleasure, in the sense in which there are various kinds of colour—blue, red, green, etc. Even in this case, if we are to say that our end is colour alone, then, although it is impossible we should have colour without having some particular colour, yet the particular colour we must have, is only a means to our having colour, if colour is really our end. And if colour is our only possible end, as Mill says pleasure is, then there can be no possible reason for preferring one colour to another, red, for instance, to blue, except that the one is more of a colour than the other. Yet the opposite of this is what Mill is attempting to hold with regard to pleasures. (§ 48 ¶ 2)
Accordingly a consideration of Mill’s view that some pleasures are
superior to others in quality brings out one point which may help to
determine the intellect
with regard to the intuition Pleasure is the only
good.
For it brings out the fact that if you say pleasure,
you must
mean pleasure
: you must mean some one thing common to all different
pleasures,
some one thing, which may exist in different degrees, but
which cannot differ in kind. I have pointed out that, if you say, as
Mill does, that quality of pleasure is to be taken into account, then you are no
longer holding that pleasure alone is good as an end, since you imply
that something else, something which is not present in all pleasures,
is also good as an end. The illustration I have given from colour
expresses this point in its most acute form. It is plain that if you say
Colour alone is good as an end,
then you can give no possible reason for
preferring one colour to another. Your only standard of good and bad will then
be colour
; and since red and blue both conform equally to this, the only
standard, you can have no other whereby to judge whether red is better than
blue. It is true that you cannot have colour unless you also have one or all of
the particular colours: they, therefore, if colour is the end, will all be good
as means, but none of them can be better than another even as a means, far less
can any one of them be regarded as an end in itself. Just so with pleasure: If
we do really mean Pleasure alone is good as an end,
then we must agree
with Bentham that Quantity of pleasure being equal, pushpin is as good as
poetry.
To have thus dismissed Mill’s reference to quality of pleasure, is
therefore to have made one step in the desired direction. The reader will now no
longer be prevented from agreeing with me, by any idea that the hedonistic
principle Pleasure alone is good as an end
is consistent with the view
that one pleasure may be of a better quality than another. These two views, we
have seen, are contradictory to one another. We must choose between them: and if
we choose the latter, then we must give up the principle of Hedonism. (§ 48 ¶ 3)