Book III: The Moral Ideal and Moral Progress.
Chapter I: Good and Moral Good.
§161.
Such interests, though not mere appetites because conditioned by
self-consciousness, correspond to them as not having pleasure for their object.
This point was sufficiently made out in the controversy as to the
disinterestedness
of benevolence, carried on during the first part of the
eighteenth century. When philosophers of the selfish school
represented
benevolence as ultimately desire for some pleasure to oneself, Butler and others
met them by showing that this was the same mistake as to reckon hunger a desire
for the pleasure of eating. The appetite of hunger must precede and condition
the pleasure which consists in its satisfaction. It cannot therefore have that
pleasure for its exciting object. It terminates upon its object,
and is
not relative to anything beyond the taking of food; and in the same way
benevolent desires terminate upon their objects, upon the benefits done to
others. In the termination
in each case there is pleasure, but it is a
confusion to represent this as an object beyond the obtaining of food or the
doing a kindness, to which the appetite or benevolent desire is really directed.
What is true of benevolence is true of motives which we opposite to it, as the
vicious to the virtuous, e.g. of jealousy or the
desire for revenge. Iago does not work upon Othello for the sake of any pleasure
that he expects to experience when his envy is gratified, but because in his
envious state an object of which the realisation seems necessary to the
satisfaction of himself is Othello’s ruin, just as the consumption of food
is necessary to the satisfaction of hunger. What he desires is to see Othello
down, not the pleasure he will feel when he sees him so—a pleasure which
he could not feel unless he had desired the object independently of such
anticipation. (§161 ¶1)
It is true that any interest or desire for an object may come to
be reinforced by desire for the pleasure which, reflecting upon past analogous
experience, the subject of the interest may expect as incidental to its
satisfaction. In this way cool self-love,
according to the terminology of
the last century, may combine with particular desires or propensions.
If
there is to be any chance, however, of the expected pleasure being really
enjoyed, the self-love
of which pleasure is the object must not supersede
the particular propension
of which pleasure, in the case of ordinary
healthy interests, is not the object. The pleasure incidental to the
satisfaction of an interest cannot be attained after loss of the interest
itself, nor can the interest be revived by wishing for a renewal of the pleasure
incidental to its satisfaction. Hence just so far as cool self-love,
in
the sense of a calculating pursuit of pleasure, becomes dominant and supersedes
particular interests, the chances of pleasure are really lost; which accounts
for the restlessness of the pleasure-seeker, and for the common remark that the
right way to get pleasure is not to seek it. (§161
¶2)