Essay II, n. 1: [Reprinted from the Journal of Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, vol. I, 1904, No. 20, September 29, and No. 21, October 13. §§ 3—5 have also been reprinted, with some omissions, alterations and additions, in The Meaning of Truth, Essay IV. The alterations have been adopted in the present text. This essay is referred to in A Pluralistic Universe, p. 280, note 5. Ed.]
It is difficult not to notice a curious unrest in the philosophic atmosphere of the time, always loosening of old landmarks, a softening of oppositions, a mutual borrowing from one another reflecting on the part of systems anciently closed, and an interest in new suggestions, however vague, as if the one thing sure were the inadequacy of the extant school-solutions. The dissatisfaction with these seems due for the most part to a feeling that they are too abstract and academic. Life is confused and superabundant, and what the younger generation appears to crave is more of the temperament of life in its philosophy, even thought it were at some cost of logical rigor and of formal purity. Transcendental idealism is inclining to let the world wag incomprehensibly, in spite of its Absolute Subject and his unity of purpose. Berkeleyan idealism is abandoning the principle of parsimony and dabbling in panpsychic speculations. Empiricism flirts with teleology; and, strangest of all, natural realism, so long decently buried, raises its head above the turf, and finds glad hands outstretched from the most unlikely quarters to help it to its feet again. We are all biased by our personal feelings, I know, and I am personally discontented with extant solutions; so I seem to read the signs of a great unsettlement, as if the upheaval of more real conceptions and more fruitful methods were imminent, as if a true landscape might result, less clipped, straight-edged and artificial. (Essay II ¶ 1)
If philosophy be really on the eve of any considerable rearrangement, the time should be propitious for any one who has suggestions of his own to bring forward. For many years past my mind has bee growing into a certain type of Weltanschauung. Rightly or wrongly, I have got to the point where I can hardly see things in any other pattern. I propose, therefore, to describe the pattern as clearly as I can consistently with great brevity, and to throw my description into the bubbling vat of publicity where, jostled by rivals and torn by critics, it will eventually either disappear from notice, or else, if better luck befall it, quietly subside to the profundities, and serve as a possible ferment of new growths or a nucleus of new crystallization. (Essay II ¶ 2)
I. Radical Empiricism
I give the name of radical empiricism
to
my Weltanschauung. Empiricism is known as
the opposite of rationalism. Rationalism tends
to emphasize universals and to make wholes
prior to parts in the order of logic as well as in
that of being. Empiricism, on the contrary,
lays the explanatory stress upon the part, the
element, the individual, and treats the whole
as a collection and the universal as an abstraction.
My description of things, accordingly,
starts with the parts and makes of the whole
a being of the second order. It is essentially
a mosaic philosophy, a philosophy of plural
facts, like that of Hume and his descendants,
who refer these facts neither to Substances in
which they inhere nor to an Absolute Mind
that creates them as its objects. But it differs
from the Humian type of empiricism in one
particular which makes me add the epithet
radical. (Essay II § 1 ¶ 1)
To be radical, an empiricism must neither
admit into its constructions any element that
is not directly experienced, nor exclude from
them any element that is directly experienced.
For such a philosophy, the relations that connect
experiences must themselves be experienced relations,
and any kind of relation experienced must
be accounted as real
as anything else in the
system. Elements may indeed be redistributed,
the original placing of things getting corrected,
but a real place must be found for every kind
of thing experienced, whether term or relation,
in the final philosophic arrangement. (Essay II § 1 ¶ 2)
Now, ordinary empiricism, in spite of the
fact that conjunctive and disjunctive relations
present themselves as being fully co-ordinate
parts of experience, has always shown a tendency
to do away with the connections of
things, and to insist most on the disjunctions.
Berkeley’s nominalism, Hume’s statement that
whatever things we distinguish are as loose
and separate
as if they had no manner of connection.
James Mill’s denial that similars have
anything really
in common, the resolution
of the causal tie into habitual sequence, John
Mill’s account of both physical things and
selves as composed of discontinuous possibilities,
and the general pulverization of all Experience
by association and the mind-dust
theory, are examples of what I mean. (Essay II § 1 ¶ 3)
The natural result of such a world-picture has been the efforts of rationalism to correct its incoherencies by the addition of trans- experiential agents of unification, substances, intellectual categories and powers, or Selves; whereas, if empiricism had only been radical and taken everything that comes without disfavor, conjunction as well as separation, each at its face value, the results would have called for no such artificial correction. Radical empiricism, as I understand it, does full justice to conjunctive relations, without, however, treating them as rationalism always tends to treat them, as being true in some supernal way, as if the unity of things and their variety belonged to different orders of truth and vitality altogether. (Essay II § 1 ¶ 4)
Essay II § 1, n. 1: [Cf. Berkeley: Principles of Human Knowledge, Introduction; Hume: An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, sect. VII, part II (Selby-Bigge’s edition, p. 74); James Mill: Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind, ch. VIII; J. S. Mill: An Examination of Sir William Hamilton’s Philosophy, ch. XI, XII; W. K. Clifford: Lectures and Essays, pp. 274 ff.] ↩
II. Conjunctive Relations
Relations are of different degrees of intimacy.
Merely to be with
one another in a
universe of discourse is the most external relation
that terms can have, and seems to involve
nothing whatever as to farther consequences.
Simultaneity and time-interval come next, and
then space-adjacency and distance. After
them, similarity and difference, carrying the
possibility of many inferences. Then relations
of activity, tying terms into series involving
change, tendency, resistance, and the causal
order generally. Finally, the relation experienced
between terms that form states of mind,
and are immediately conscious of continuing
each other. The organization of the Self as a
system of memories, purposes, strivings, fulfilments
or disappointments, is incidental to
this most intimate of all relations, the terms
of which seem in many cases actually to compenetrate
and suffuse each other’s being. (Essay II § 2 ¶ 1)
Philosophy has always turned on grammatical particles. With, near, next, like, from, towards, against, because, for, through, my — these words designate types of conjunctive relation arranged in a roughly ascending order of intimacy and inclusiveness. A priori, we can imagine a universe of withness but no nextness; or one of nextness but no likeness, or of likeness with no activity, or of activity with no purpose, or of purpose with no ego. These would be universes, each with its own grade of unity. The universe of human experience is, by one or another of its parts, of each and all these grades. Whether or not it possibly enjoys some still more absolute grade of union does not appear upon the surface. (Essay II § 2 ¶ 2)
Taken as it does appear, our universe is to a large extent chaotic. No one single type of connection runs through all the experiences that compose it. If we take space-relations, they fail to connect minds into any regular system. Causes and purposes obtain only among special series of facts. The self-relation seems extremely limited and does not link two different selves together. Prima facie, if you should liken the universe of absolute idealism to an aquarium, a crystal globe in which goldfish are swimming, you would have to compare the empiricist universe to something more like one of those dried human heads with which the Dyaks of Borneo deck their lodges. The skull forms a solid nucleus; but innumerable feathers, leaves, strings, beads, and loose appendices of every description float and dangle from it, and, save that they terminate in it, seem to have nothing to do with one another. Even so my experiences and yours float and dangle, terminating, it is true, in a nucleus of common perception, but for the most part out of sight and irrelevant and unimaginable to one another. This imperfect intimacy, this bare relation of withness between some parts of the sum total of experience and other parts, is the fact that ordinary empiricism over-emphasizes against rationalism, the latter always tending to ignore it unduly. Radical empiricism, on the contrary, is fair to both the unity and the disconnection. It finds no reason for treating either as illusory. It allots to each its definite sphere of description, and agrees that there appear to be actual forces at work which tend, as time goes on, to make the unity greater. (Essay II § 2 ¶ 3)
The conjunctive relation that has given
most trouble to philosophy is the co-conscious
transition, so to call it, by which one experience
passes into another when both belong to the
same self. My experiences and your experiences are
with
each other in various external ways, but
mine pass into mine, and yours pass into yours
in a way in which yours and mine never pass
into one another. Within each of our personal
histories, subject, object, interest and purpose
are continuous or may be continuous. Personal
histories are processes of change in time, and
the change itself is one of the things immediately
experienced. Change
in this case means continuous
as opposed to discontinuous transition.
But continuous transition is one sort of a
conjunctive relation; and to be a radical empiricist
means to hold fast to this conjunctive
relation of all others, for this is the strategic
point, the position through which, if a hole be
made, all the corruptions of dialectics and all
the metaphysical fictions pour into our philosophy.
The holding fast to this relation means
taking it at its face value, neither less nor more;
and to take it at its face value means first of all
to take it just as we feel it, and not to confuse
ourselves with abstract talk about it, involving
words that drive us to invent secondary
conceptions in order to neutralize their
suggestions and to make our actual experience
again seem rationally possible. (Essay II § 2 ¶ 4)
What I do feel simply when a later moment of my experience succeeds an earlier one is that though they are two moments, the transition from the one to the other is continuous. Continuity here is a definite sort of experience; just as definite as is the discontinuity-experience which I find it impossible to avoid when I seek to make the transition from an experience of my own to one of yours. In this latter case I have to get on and off again, to pass from a thing lived to another thing only conceived, and the break is positively experienced and noted. Though the functions exerted by my experience and by yours may be the same (e.g., the same objects known and the same purposes followed), yet the sameness has in this case to be ascertained expressly (and often with difficulty and uncertainly) after the break has been felt; whereas in passing from one of my own moments to another the sameness of object and interest is unbroken, and both the earlier and the later experience are of things directly lived. (Essay II § 2 ¶ 5)
There is no other nature, no other whatness
than this absence of break and this sense of
continuity in that most intimate of all conjunctive
relations, the passing of one experience
into another when the belong to the same self.
And this whatness is real empirical content,
just as the whatness of separation and discontinuity
is real content in the contrasted case.
Practically to experience one’s personal continuum
in this living way is to know the originals
of the ideas of continuity and sameness, to
know what the words stand for concretely, to
own all that they can ever mean. But all experiences
have their conditions; and over-subtle
intellects, thinking about the facts here, and
asking how they are possible, have ended by
substituting a lot of static objects of conception
for the direct perceptual experiences.
Sameness,
they have said, must be a stark
numerical identity; it can’t run on from next to
next. Continuity can’t mean mere absence of
gap; for if you say two things are in immediate
contact, at the contact how can they be two?
If, on the other hand, you put a relation of
transition between them, that itself is a third
thing, and needs to be related or hitched to its
terms. An infinite series is involved,
and so
on. The result is that from difficulty to difficulty,
the plain conjunctive experience has
been discredited by both schools, the empiricists
leaving things permanently disjoined, and
the rationalist remedying the looseness by their
Absolutes or Substances, or whatever other fictitious
agencies of union may have employed. From all which artificiality we can
be saved by a couple of simple-reflections: first,
that conjunctions and separations are, at all
events, co-ordinate phenomena which, if we
take experiences at their face value, must be
accounted equally real; and second, that if we
insist on treating things as really separate
when they are given as continuously joined,
invoking, when union is required, transcendental
principles to overcome the separateness
we have assumed, then we ought to stand
ready to perform the converse act. We ought
to invoke higher principles of disunion, also, to
make our merely experienced disjunctions more
truly real. Failing thus, we ought to let the
originally given continuities stand on their own
bottom. We have no right to be lopsided or to
blow capriciously hot and cold. (Essay II § 2 ¶ 6)
Essay II § 2, n. 1: [See The Experience of Activity, below, pp. 155-189.] ↩
Essay II § 2, n. 2: The psychology books have of late described the facts here with
approximate adequacy. I may refer to the chapters on The Stream of
Thought
and on the Self in my own Principles of Psychology, as well as to S.H. Hodgson’s Metaphysics of Experience, vol I., ch. VII and VIII. ↩
Essay II § 3, n. 3: [See The Thing and its Relations, below, pp. 92-122.] ↩
III. The Cognitive Relation
The first great pitfall from which such a radical
standing by experience will save us is an
artificial conception of the relations between
knower and known. Throughout the history of
philosophy the subject and its object have been
treated as absolutely discontinuous entities;
and thereupon the presence of the latter to the
former, or the apprehension
by the former of
the latter, has assumed a paradoxical character
which all sorts of theories had to be invented
to overcome. Representative theories
put a mental representation,
image,
or
content
into the gap, as a sort of intermediary.
Common-sense theories left the gap
untouched, declaring our mind able to clear
it by a self-transcending leap. Transcendentalist
theories left it impossible to traverse by
finite knowers, and brought an Absolute in to
perform the saltatory act. All the while, in
the very bosom of the finite experience, every
conjunction required to make the relation intelligible
is given in full. Either the knower
and the known are: (Essay II § 3 ¶ 1)
the self-same piece of experience taken twice over in different contexts; or they are (Essay II § 3 ¶ 2)
two pieces of actual experience belonging to the same subject, with definite tracts of conjunctive transitional experience between them; or (Essay II § 3 ¶ 3)
the known is a possible experience either of that subject or another, to which the said conjunctive transitions would lead, if sufficiently prolonged. (Essay II § 3 ¶ 4)
To discuss all the ways in which one experience may function as the knower of another,
would be incompatible with the limits
of this essay. I have just treated of type 1, the
kind of knowledge called perception. This is
the type of case in which the mind enjoys direct
acquaintance
with a present object. In
the other types the mind has knowledge-about
an object not immediately there. Of
type 2, the simplest sort of conceptual knowledge,
I have given some account in two [earlier]
articles. Type 3 can always formally
and hypothetically be reduced to type 2, so
that a brief description of that type will put
the present reader sufficiently at my point
of view, and make him see what the actual
meanings of the mysterious cognitive relation
may be. (Essay II § 3 ¶ 5)
Suppose me to be sitting here in my library
at Cambridge, at ten minutes’ walk from
Memorial Hall,
and to be thinking truly of
the latter object. My mind may have before
it only the name, or it may have a clear image,
or it may have a very dim image of the hall, but
such intrinsic differences in the image make no
difference in its cognitive function. Certain
extrinsic phenomena, special experiences of
conjunction, are what impart to the image, be
it what it may, its knowing office. (Essay II § 3 ¶ 6)
For instance, if you ask me what hall I mean
by my image, and I call tell you nothing; or if I
fail to point or lead you towards the Harvard
Delta; or if, being led by you, I am uncertain
whether the Hall I see be what I had in mind
or not; you would rightly deny that I had
meant
that particular hall at all, even though
my mental image might to some degree have
resembled it. The resemblance would count in
that case as coincidental merely, for all sorts
of things of a kind resemble one another in this
world without being held for that reason to
take cognizance of one another. (Essay II § 3 ¶ 7)
On the other hand, if I can lead you to the hall, and tell you of its history and present uses; if in its presence I feel my idea, however imperfect it may have been, to have led hither and to be now terminated; if the associates of the image and of the felt hall run parallel, so that each term of the one context corresponds serially, as I walk, with an answering term of the others; why then my soul was prophetic, and my idea must be, and by common consent would be, called cognizant of reality. That percept was what I meant, for into it my idea has passed by conjunctive experiences of sameness and fulfilled intention. Nowhere is there jar, but every later moment continues and corroborates an earlier one. (Essay II § 3 ¶ 8)
In this continuing and corroborating, taken
in no transcendental sense, but denoting definitely
felt transitions, lies all that the knowing
of a percept by an idea can possibly contain or
signify. Wherever such transitions are felt, the
first experience knows that last one. Where they
do not, or where even as possibles they can not,
intervene, there can be no pretence of knowing.
In this latter case the extremes will be connected,
if connected at all, by inferior relations
— bare likeness or succession, or by withness
alone. Knowledge of sensible realities thus
comes to life inside the tissue of experience. It
is made; and made by relations that unroll
themselves in time. Whenever certain intermediaries
are given, such that, as they develop
towards their terminus, there is experience
from point to point of one direction followed,
and finally of one process fulfilled, the result
is that their starting-point thereby becomes a
knower and their terminus an object meant or
known. That is all that knowing (in the simple
case considered) can be known-as, that is
the whole of its nature, put into experiential
terms. Whenever such is the sequence of our
experiences we may freely say that we had the
terminal object in mind
from the outset, even
although at the outset nothing was there in us
but a flat piece of substantive experience like
any other, with no self-transcendency about it,
and ny mystery save the mystery of coming
into existence and of being gradually followed
by other pieces of substantive experience, with
conjunctively transitional experiences between.
That is what we mean here by the object’s
being in mind.
Of any deeper more real way
of being in mind we have no positive conception,
and we have no right to discredit our
actual experience by talking of such a way
at all. (Essay II § 3 ¶ 9)
I know that many a reader will rebel at this.
Mere intermediaries,
he will say, even
though they be feelings of continuously growing
fulfilment, only separate the knower from
the known, whereas what we have in knowledge
is a kind of immediate touch of the one by the
other, an
(Essay II § 3 ¶ 10)apprehension
in the etymological
sense of the word, a leaping of the chasm as by
lightning, an act by which two terms are smitten
into one, over the head of their distinctness.
All these dead intermediaries of yours
are out of each other, and outside of their
termini still.
But do not such dialectic difficulties remind
us of the dog dropping his bone and snapping
at its image in the water? If we knew any more
real kind of union aliunde, we might be entitled
to brand all our empirical unions as a sham.
But unions by continuous transition are the
only ones we know of, whether in this matter
of a knowledge-about that terminates in an
acquaintance, whether in personal identity, in
logical predication through the copula is,
or
elsewhere. If anywhere there were more absolute
unions realized, they could only reveal
themselves to us by just such conjunctive
results. These are what the unions are worth,
these are all that we can ever practically mean
by union, by continuity. Is it not time to
repeat what Lotze said of substances, that to
act like one is to be one? Should we not say
here that to be experienced as continuous is to
be really continuous, in a world where experience
and reality come to the same thing? In
a picture gallery a painted hook will serve to
hang a painted chain by, a painted cable will
hold a painted ship. In a world where both the
terms and their distinctions are affairs of experience,
conjunctions that are experienced
must be at least as real as anything else. They
will be absolutely
real conjunctions, if we have
no transphenomenal Absolute ready, to derealize
the whole experienced world by, at a stroke.
If, on the other hand, we had such an Absolute,
not one of our opponents’ theories of knowledge
could remain standing any better than
ours could; for the distinctions as well as the
conjunctions of experience would impartially
fall its prey. The whole question of how one
thing can know another
would cease to be a
real one at all in a world where otherness itself
was an illusion. (Essay II § 3 ¶ 11)
So much for the essentials of the cognitive
relation, where the knowledge is conceptual in
type, or forms knowledge about
an object. It
consists in intermediary experiences (possible,
if not actual) of continuously developing progress,
and, finally, of fulfilment, when the sensible
percept, which is the object, is reached.
The percept here not only verifies the concept,
proves its function of knowing that percept to
be true, but the percept’s existence as the
terminus of the chain of intermediaries creates
the function. Whatever terminates that chain
was, because it now proves itself to be, what
the concept had in mind.
(Essay II § 3 ¶ 12)
The towering importance for human life of
this kind of knowing lies in the fact that an
experience that knows another can figure as
its representative, not in any quasi-miraculous
epistemological
sense, but in the definite
practical sense of being its substitute in various
operations, sometimes physical and sometimes
mental, which lead us to its associates and results.
By experimenting on our ideas of reality,
we may save ourselves the trouble of experimenting
on the real experiences which they
severally mean. The ideas form related systems,
corresponding point for point to the systems
which the realities form; and by letting an
ideal term call up its associates systematically,
we may be led to a terminus which the corresponding
real term would have led to in case
we had operated on the real world. And this
brings us to the general question of substitution. (Essay II § 3 ¶ 13)
Essay II § 3, n. 1: For brevity’s sake I altogether omit mention of the type
constituted by knowledge of the truth of general propositions. This
type has been thoroughly and, so far as I can see, satisfactorily,
elucidated in Dewey’s Studies in Logical Theory. Such propositions
are reducible to the S-is-P form; and the terminus
that verifies and
fulfils is the SP in combination. Of course percepts may be involved in
the mediating experiences, or in the satisfactoriness
of the P in its
new position. ↩
Essay II § 3, n. 2: [See above, Does Consciousness Exist?, § 2.] ↩
Essay II § 3, n. 3: [On the Function of Cognition, Mind, vol. X, 1885, and The Knowing of Things Together, Psychological Review, vol. II, 1895. These articles are reprinted, the former in full, the latter in part, in The Meaning of Truth, pp. 1-50. Ed.] These articles and their doctrine, unnoticed apparently by any one else, have lately gained favorable comment from Professor Strong. [A Naturalistic Theory of the Reference of Thought to Reality, Journal of Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, vol. I, 1904.] Dr. Dickinson S. Miller has independently thought out the same results [The Meaning of Truth and Error, Philosophical Review, vol. II, 1893; The Confusion of Function and Content in Mental Analysis, Psychological Review, vol. II, 1895], which Strong accordingly dubs the James-Miller theory of cognition. ↩
Essay II § 3, n. 4: [Cf. H. Lotze: Metaphysik, §§ 37-39, 97, 98, 243.] ↩
Essay II § 3, n. 5: Mr. Bradley, not professing to know his absolute aliunde, nevertheless derealizes Experience by alleging it to be everywhere infected with self-contradiction. His arguments seem almost purely verbal, but this is no place for arguing that point out. [Cf. F. H. Bradley; Appearance and Reality, passim; and below, pp. 106-122.] ↩
IV. Substitution
In Taine’s brilliant book on Intelligence,
substitution was for the first time named as
a cardinal logical function, though of course
the facts had always been familiar enough.
What, exactly, in a system of experiences, does
the substitution
of one of them for another
mean? (Essay II § 4 ¶ 1)
According to my view, experience as a whole
is a process in time, whereby innumerable
particular terms lapse and are superseded by
others that follow upon them by transitions
which, whether disjunctive or conjunctive in
content, are themselves experiences, and must
in general be accounted at least as real as
the terms which they relate. What the nature
of the event called superseding
signifies, depends
altogether on the kind of transition
that obtains. Some experiences simply abolish
their predecessors without continuing them
in any way. Others are felt to increase or to
enlarge their meaning, to carry out their purpose,
or to bring us nearer to their goal. They
represent
them, and may fulfil their function
better than they fulfilled it themselves. But to
fulfil a function
in a world of pure experience
can be conceived and defined in only one possible
way. In such a world transitions and
arrivals (or terminations) are the only events
that happen, though they happen by so many
sorts of path. The only experience that one experience
can perform is to lead into another
experience; and the only fulfilment we can
speak of is the reaching of a certain experienced
end. When one experience leads to (or
can lead to) the same end as another, they
agree in function. But the whole system of
experiences as they are immediately given
presents itself as a quasi-chaos through which
one can pass out of an initial term in many
directions and yet end in the same terminus,
moving from next to next by a great many
possible paths. (Essay II § 4 ¶ 2)
Either one of these paths might be a functional
substitute for another, and to follow one
rather than another might on occasion be
an advantageous thing to do. As a matter of
fact, and in a general way, the paths that
run through conceptual experiences, that is,
through thoughts
or ideas
that know
the
things in which they terminate, are highly advantageous
paths to follow. Not only do they
yield inconceivably rapid transitions; but, owing
to the universal
character which they
frequently possess, and to their capacity for
association with one another in great systems,
they outstrip the tardy consecutions of the
things themselves, and sweep us on towards
our ultimate termini in a far more labor-saving
way than the following of trains of sensible
perception ever could. Wonderful are the new
cuts and the short-circuits which the thought-
paths make. Most thought-paths, it is true,
are substitutes for nothing actual; they end
outside the real world altogether, in wayward
fancies, utopias, fictions or mistakes. But
where they do re-enter reality and terminate
therein, we substitute them always; and with
these substitutes we pass the greater number
of our hours. (Essay II § 4 ¶ 3)
This is why I called our experiences, taken
together, a quasi-chaos. There is vastly
more discontinuity in the sum total of experiences
than we commonly suppose. The objective
nucleus of every man’s experience, his own
body, is, it is true, a continuous percept; and
equally continuous as a percept (thought we
may be inattentive to it) is the material environment
of that body, changing by gradual
transition when the body moves. But the
distant parts of the physical world are at all
times absent from us, and form conceptual
objects merely, into the perceptual reality of
which our life inserts itself at points discrete
and relatively rare. Round their several objective
nuclei, partly shared and common and
partly discrete, of the real physical world, innumerable
thinkers, pursuing their several lines
of physically true cogitation, trace paths that
intersect one another only at discontinuous
perceptual points, and the rest of the time are
quite incongruent; and around all the nuclei
of shared reality,
as around the Dyak’s head
of my late metaphor, floats the vast cloud of
experiences that are wholly subjective, that
are non-substitutional, that find not even an
eventual ending for themselves in the perceptual
world — there mere day-dreams and
joys and sufferings and wishes of the individual
minds. These exist with one another, indeed,
and with the objective nuclei, but out
of them it is probable that to all eternity no
interrelated system of any kind will every be
made. (Essay II § 4 ¶ 4)
This notion of the purely substitutional or conceptual physical world brings us to the most critical of all steps in the development of a philosophy of pure experience. The paradox of self-transcendency in knowledge comes back upon us here, but I think that our notions of pure experience and of substitution, and our radically empirical view of conjunctive transitions, are Denkmittel that will carry us safely through the pass. (Essay II § 4 ¶ 5)
Essay II § 4, n. 1: Of which all that need be said in this essay is that it also can be conceived as functional, and defined in terms of transitions, or of the possibility of such. [Cf. Principles of Psychology, vol. I, pp. 473-480, vol. II, pp. 337-340; Pragmatism, p. 265; Some Problems of Philosophy, pp. 63-74; Meaning of Truth, pp. 246-247, etc. Ed.] ↩
V. What Objective Reference Is.
Whosoever feels his experience to be something
substitutional even while he has it, may
be said to have an experience that reaches
beyond itself. From inside of its own entity it
says more,
and postulates reality existing elsewhere.
For the transcendentalist, who holds
knowing to consist in a salto mortale across an
epistemological chasm,
such an idea presents
no difficulty; but it seems at first sight as if it
might be inconsistent with an empiricism like
our own. Have we not explained that conceptual
knowledge is made such wholly by the
existence of things that fall outside of the
knowing experience itself — by intermediary
experience and by a terminus that fulfils?
Can the knowledge be there before these elements
that constitute its being have come?
And, if knowledge be not there, how can objective
reference occur? (Essay II § 5 ¶ 1)
The key to this difficulty lies in the distinction
between knowing as verified and completed,
and the same knowing as in transit
and on its way. To recur to the Memorial
Hall example lately used, it is only when our
idea of the Hall has actually terminated in the
percept that we know for certain
that from
the beginning it was truly cognitive of that.
Until established by the end of the process, its
quality of knowing that, or indeed of knowing
anything, could still be doubted; and yet the
knowing really was there, as the result now
shows. We were virtual knowers of the Hall
long before we were certified to have been its
actual knowers, by the percept’s retroactive
validating power. Just so we are mortal
all
the time, by reason of the virtuality of the
inevitable event which will make us so when
it shall have come. (Essay II § 5 ¶ 2)
Now the immensely greater part of all our
knowing never gets beyond this virtual stage.
It never is completed or nailed down. I speak
not merely of our ideas of imperceptibles like
ether-waves or dissociated ions,
or of ejects
like the contents of our neighbors’ minds; I
speak also of ideas which we might verify if we
would take the trouble, but which we hold for
true although unterminated perceptually, because
nothing says no
to us, and there is no
contradicting truth in sight. To continue thinking
unchallenged is, ninety-nine times out of a
hundred, our practical substitute for knowing in
the completed sense. As each experience runs by
cognitive transition into the next one, and we
nowhere feel a collision with what we elsewhere
count as truth or fact, we commit ourselves to
the current as if the port were sure. We live,
as it were, upon the front edge of an advancing
wave-crest, and our sense of a determinate
direction in falling forward is all we cover of
the future of our path. It is as if a differential
quotient should be conscious and treat itself as
an adequate substitute for a traced-out curve.
Our experience, inter alia, is of variations of
rate and of direction, and lives in these transitions
more than in the journey’s end. The experiences
of tendency are sufficient to act upon
— what more could we have done at those
moments even if the later verification comes
complete? (Essay II § 5 ¶ 3)
This is what, as a radical empiricist, I say to
the charge that the objective reference which
is so flagrant a character of our experience involves
a chasm and a mortal leap. A positively
conjunctive transition involves neither chasm
nor leap. Being the very original of what we
mean by continuity, it makes a continuum
wherever it appears. I know full well that such
brief words as these will leave the hardened
transcendentalist unshaken. Conjunctive experiences
separate their terms, he will still say: they
are third things interposed, that have themselves
to be conjoined by new links, and to invoke
them makes our trouble infinitely worse.
To feel
our motion forward is impossible.
Motion implies terminus; and how can terminus
be felt before we have arrived? The barest
start and sally forwards, the barest tendency
to leave the instant, involves the chasm and
the leap. Conjunctive transitions are the most
superficial of appearances, illusions of our sensibility
which philosophical reflection pulverizes
at a touch. Conception is our only trustworthy
instrument, conception and the Absolute
working hand in hand. Conception disintegrates
experience utterly, but its disjunctions
are easily overcome again when the Absolute
takes up the task. (Essay II § 5 ¶ 4)
Such transcendentalists I must leave, provisionally at least, in full possession of their creed. I have no space for polemics in this article, so I shall simply formulate the empiricist doctrine as my hypothesis, leaving it to work or not work as it may. (Essay II § 5 ¶ 5)
Objective reference, I say then, is an incident
of the fact that so much of our experience
comes as an insufficient and consists of
process and transition. Our fields of experience
have no more definite boundaries than have
our fields of view. Both are fringed forever by
a more that continuously develops, and that
continuously supersedes them as life proceeds.
The relations, generally speaking, are as real
here as the terms are, and the only complaint
of the transcendentalist’s with which I could
at all sympathize would be his charge that, by
first making knowledge consist in external
relations as I have done, and by then confessing
that nine-tenths of the time these are
not actually but only virtually there, I have
knocked the solid bottom out of the whole
business, and palmed off a substitute of knowledge
for the genuine thing. Only the admission,
such a critic might say, that our ideas are
self-transcendent and true
already, in advance
of the experiences that are to terminate
them, can bring solidity back to knowledge
in a world like this, in which transitions and
terminations are only by exception fulfilled. (Essay II § 5 ¶ 6)
This seems to me an excellent place for applying the pragmatic method. When a dispute arises, that method consists in auguring what practical consequences would be different if one side rather than the other were true. If no difference can be thought of, the dispute is a quarrel over words. What then would the self-transcendency affirmed to exist in advance of all experiential mediation or terminations, be known-as? What would it practically result in for us, were it true? (Essay II § 5 ¶ 7)
It could only result in our orientation, in the
turning of our expectations and practical tendencies
into the right path; and the right path
here, so long as we and the object are not yet
face to face (or can never get face to face, as in
the case of ejects), would be the path that led
us into the object’s nearest neighborhood.
Where direct acquaintance is lacking, knowledge
about
is the next best thing, and an
acquaintance with what actually lies about the
object, and is most closely related to it, puts
such knowledge within our gasp. Ether-waves
and your anger, for example, are things in
which my thoughts will never perceptually terminate,
but my concepts of them lead me to
their very brink, to the chromatic fringes and
to the hurtful words and deeds which are their
really next effects. (Essay II § 5 ¶ 8)
Even if our ideas did in themselves carry the postulated self-transcendency, it would still remain true that their putting us into possession of such effects would be the sole cash-value of the self-transcendency for us. And this cash-value, it is needless to say, is verbatim et literatim what our empiricist account pays in. On pragmatist principles, therefore, a dispute over self-transcendency is a pure logomachy. Call our concepts of ejective things self- transcendent or the reverse, it makes no difference, so long as we don’t differ about the nature of that exalted virtue’s fruits — fruits for us, of course, humanistic fruits. If an Absolute were proved to exist for other reasons, it might well appear that his knowledge is terminated in innumerable cases where ours is still incomplete. That, however, would be a fact indifferent to our knowledge. The latter would grow neither worse nor better, whether we acknowledged such an Absolute or left him out. (Essay II § 5 ¶ 9)
So the notion of a knowledge still in transitu
and on its way joins hands here with that
notion of a pure experience
which I tried to
explain in my [essay] entitled Does Consciousness Exist? The instant field of the
present is always experienced in its pure
state.
plain unqualified actuality, a simple that, as yet
undifferentiated into thing and thought, and
only virtually classifiable as objective fact or as
some one’s opinion about fact. This is as true
when the field is conceptual as when it is perceptual.
Memorial Hall
is there
in my idea
as much as when I stand before it. I proceed to
act on its account in either case. Only in the
later experience that supersedes the present
one is this naïf immediacy retrospectively split
into two parts, a consciousness
and its content,
and the content corrected or confirmed.
While still pure, or present, any experience —
mine, for example, of what I write about in
these very lines — passes for truth.
The
morrow may reduce it to opinion.
The transcendentalist
in all his particular knowledges is
as liable to this reduction as I am: his Absolute
does not save him. Why, then, need he quarrel
with an account of knowing that merely leaves
it liable to this inevitable condition? Why insist
that knowing is a static relation out of
time when it practically seems so much a function
of our active life? For a thing to be valid,
says Lotze, is the same as to make itself
valid. When the whole universe seems only
to be making itself valid and to be still incomplete
(else why its ceaseless changing?) why, of
all things, should knowing be exempt? Why
should it not be making itself valid like everything
else? That some parts of it may be already
valid or verified beyond dispute, the
empirical philosopher, of course, like any one
else, may always hope. (Essay II § 5 ¶ 10)
Essay II § 5, n. 1: [Cf. below, pp. 93ff.] ↩
VI. The Conterminousness of Different Minds
With transition and prospect thus enthroned in pure experience, it is impossible to subscribe to the idealism of the English school. Radical empiricism has, in fact, more affinities with natural realism than with the views of Berkeley or of Mill, and this can be easily shown. (Essay II § 6 ¶ 1)
For the Berkeleyan school, ideas (the verbal equivalent of what I term experiences) are discontinuous. The content of each is wholly immanent, and there are no transitions with which they are consubstantial and through which their beings may unite. Your Memorial Hall and mine, even when both are percepts, are wholly out of connection with each other. Our lives are a congeries of solipsisms, out of which in strict logic only a God could compose a universe even of discourse. No dynamic currents run between my objects and your objects. Never can our minds meet in the same. (Essay II § 6 ¶ 2)
The incredibility of such a philosophy is
flagrant. It is cold, strained, and unnatural
in a supreme degree; and it may be doubted
whether even Berkeley himself, who took it
so religiously, really believed, when walking
through the streets of London, that his spirit
and the spirits of his fellow wayfarers had
absolutely different towns in view. (Essay II § 6 ¶ 3)
To me the decisive reason in favor of our
minds meeting in some common objects at least
is that, unless I make that supposition, I have
no motive for assuming that your mind exists
at all. Why do I postulate your mind? Because
I see your body acting in a certain way.
Its gestures, facial movements, words and conduct
generally, are expressive,
so I deem it
actuated as my own is, by an inner life like
mine. This argument from analogy is my reason,
whether an instinctive belief runs before it
or not. But what is your body
here but a
percept in my field? It is only as animating
that object, my object, that I have any occasion
to think of you at all. If the body that you
actuate be not the very body that I see there,
but some duplicate body of your own with
which that has nothing to do, we belong to
different universes, you and I, and for me to
speak of you is folly. Myriads of such universes
even now may coexist, irrelevant to one
another; my concern is solely with the universe
with which my own life is connected. (Essay II § 6 ¶ 4)
In that perceptual part of my universe which I call your body, your mind and my mind meet and may be called conterminous. Your mind actuates that body and mine sees it; my thoughts pass into it as into their harmonious cognitive fulfilment; your emotions and volitions pass into it as causes into their effects. (Essay II § 6 ¶ 5)
But that percept hangs together with all our other physical percepts. They are of one stuff with it; and if it be our common possession, they must be so likewise. For instance, your hand lays hold of one end of a rope and my hand lays hold of the other end. We pull against each other. Can our two hands be mutual objects in this experience, and the rope not be mutual also? What is true of the rope is true of any other percept. Your objects are over and over again the same as mine. If I ask you where some object of yours is, our old Memorial Hall, for example, you point to my Memorial Hall with your hand which I see. If you alter an object in your world, put out a candle, for example, when I am present, my candle ipso facto goes out. It is only as altering my objects that I guess you to exist. If your objects do not coalesce with my objects, if they be not identically where mine are, they must be proved to be positively somewhere else. But no other location can be assigned for them, so their place must be what it seems to be, the same. (Essay II § 6 ¶ 6)
Practically, then, our minds meet in a world
of objects which they share in common, which
would still be there, if one or several of the
minds were destroyed. I can see no formal
objection to this supposition’s being literally
true. On the principles which I am defending,
a mind
or personal consciousness
is the
name for a series of experiences run together by
certain definite transitions, and an objective
reality is a series of similar experiences knit by
different transitions. If one and the same experience
can figure twice, once in a mental and
once in a physical context (as I have tried, in
my article on Consciousness, to show that it
can), one does not see why it might not figure
thrice, or four times, or any number of times,
by running into as many different mental contexts,
just as the same point, lying at their
intersection, can be continued into many different
lines. Abolishing any number of contexts
would not destroy the experience itself
or its other contexts, any more than abolishing
some of the point’s linear continuations
would destroy the others, or destroy the point
itself. (Essay II § 6 ¶ 7)
I well know the subtle dialectic which insists
that a term taken in another relation must
needs be an intrinsically different term. The
crux is always the old Greek one, that the same
man can’t be tall in relation to one neighbor,
and short in relation to another, for that would
make him tall and short at once. In this essay
I can not stop to refute this dialectic, so I pass
on, leaving my flank for the time exposed.
But if my reader will only allow that the same
now
both ends his past and begins his future;
or that, when he buys an acre of land from his
neighbor, it is the same acre that successively
figures in the two estates; or that when I pay
him a dollar, the same dollar goes into his
pocket that came out of mine; he will also in
consistency have to allow that the same object
may conceivably play a part in, as being related
to the rest of, any number of otherwise
entirely different minds. This is enough for
my present point: the common-sense notion of
minds sharing the same object offers no special
logical or epistemological difficulties of its
own; it stands or falls with the general possibility
of things being in conjunctive relation with
other things at all. (Essay II § 6 ¶ 8)
In principle, then, let natural realism pass
for possible. Your mind and mine may terminate
in the same percept, not merely against it,
as if it were a third external thing, but by inserting
themselves into it and coalescing with
it, for such is the sort of conjunctive union that
appears to be experienced when a perceptual
terminus fulfils.
Even so, two hawsers may
embrace the same pile, and yet neither one of
them touch any other part except that pile, of
what the other hawser is attached to. (Essay II § 6 ¶ 9)
It is therefore not a formal question, but
a question of empirical fact solely, whether
when you and I are said to know the same
Memorial Hall, our minds do terminate at or in
a numerically identical percept. Obviously, as
a plain matter of fact, they do not. Apart from
color-blindness and such possibilities, we see
the Hall in different perspectives. You may be
on one side of it and I on another. The percept
of each of us, as he sees the surface of the Hall,
is moreover only his provisional terminus. The
next thing beyond my percept is not your
mind, but more percepts of my own into which
my first percept develops, the interior of the
Hall, for instance, or the inner structure of its
bricks and mortar. If our minds were in a
literal sense conterminous, neither could get
beyond the percept which they had in common,
it would be an ultimate barrier between
them — unless indeed they flowed over it and
became co-conscious
over a still larger part
of their content, which (thought-transference
apart) is not supposed to be the case. In point
of fact the ultimate common barrier can always
be pushed, by both minds, farther than any
actual percept of either, until at last it resolves
itself into the mere notion of imperceptibles
like atoms or either, so that, where we do terminate
in percepts, our knowledge is only speciously
completed, being, in theoretic strictness,
only a virtual knowledge of those remoter
objects which conception carries out. (Essay II § 6 ¶ 10)
Is natural realism, permissible in logic, refuted then by empirical fact? Do our minds have no object in common after all? (Essay II § 6 ¶ 11)
Yet, they certainly have Space in common.
On pragmatic principles we are obliged to predicate
sameness wherever we can predicate no
assignable point of difference. If two named
things have every quality and function indiscernible,
and are at the same time in the same
place, they must be written down as numerically
one thing under two different names. But
there is no test discoverable, so far as I know,
by which it can be shown that the place occupied
by your percept of Memorial Hall differs
from the place occupied by mine. The percepts
themselves may be shown to differ; but
if each of us be asked to point out where his
percept is, we point to an identical spot. All
the relations, whether geometrical or causal, of
the Hall originate or terminate in that spot
wherein our hands meet, and where each of us
begins to work if he wishes to make the Hall
change before the other’s eyes. Just so it is
with our bodies. That body of yours which
you actuate and feel from within must be in
the same spot as the body of yours which I see
or touch from without. There
for me means
where I place my finger. If you do not feel my
finger’s contact to be there
in my sense, when
I place it on your body, where then do you feel
it? Your inner actuations of your body meet
my finger there: it is there that you resist its
push, or shrink back, or sweep the finger aside
with your hand. Whatever farther knowledge
either of us may acquire of the real constitution
of the body which we thus feel, you from
within and I from without, it is in that same
place that the newly conceived or perceived
constituents have to be located, and it is
through that space that your and my mental
intercourse with each other has always to be
carried on, by the mediation of impressions
which I convey thither, and of the reactions
thence which those impressions may provoke
from you. (Essay II § 6 ¶ 12)
In general terms, then, whatever differing contents our minds may eventually fill a place with, the place itself is a numerically identical content of the two minds, a piece of common property in which, through which, and over which they join. The receptacle of certain of our experiences being thus common, the experiences themselves might some day become common also. If that day ever did come, our thoughts would terminate in a complete empirical identity, there would be an end, so far as those experiences went, to our discussions about truth. No points of difference appearing, they would have to count as the same. (Essay II § 6 ¶ 13)
Essay II § 6, n. 1: [Cf, How Two Minds Can Know One Thing, below, pp. 123-136.] ↩
Essay II § 6, n. 2: The notions that our objects are inside of our respective heads is not seriously defensible, so I pass it by. ↩
Essay II § 6, n. 3: [The argument is resumed below, pp. 101 sq. Ed.] ↩
VII. Conclusion
With this we have the outlines of a philosophy
of pure experience before us. At the outset
of my essay, I called it a mosaic philosophy.
In actual mosaics the pieces are held together
by their bedding, for which bedding of the Substances,
transcendental Egos, or Absolutes of
other philosophies may be taken to stand. In
radical empiricism there is no bedding; it is as
if the pieces clung together by their edges, the
transitions experienced between them forming
their cement. Of course such a metaphor is
misleading, for in actual experience the more
substantive and the more transitive parts run
into each other continuously, there is in general
no separateness needing to be overcome by an
external cement; and whatever separateness
is actually experienced is not overcome, it
stays and counts as separateness to the end.
But the metaphor serves to symbolize the fact
that Experience itself, taken at large, can grow
by its edges. That one moment of it proliferates
into the next by transitions which,
whether conjunctive or disjunctive, continue
the experiential tissue, can no, I contend, be
denied. Life is in the transitions as much as in
the terms connected; often, indeed, it seems to
be there more emphatically, as if our spurts
and sallies forward were the real firing-line of
the battle, were like the thin line of flame advancing
across the dry autumnal field which
the farmer proceeds to burn. In this line we
live prospectively as well as retrospectively.
It is of
the past, inasmuch as it comes expressly
as the past’s continuation; it is of
the
future in so far as the future, when it comes,
will have continued it. (Essay II § 7 ¶ 1)
These relations of continuous transition experienced
are what make our experiences cognitive.
In the simplest and completest cases
the experiences are cognitive of one another.
When one of them terminates a previous series
of them with a sense of fulfilment, it, we say,
is what those other experiences had in view.
The knowledge, in such a case, is verified; the
truth is salted down.
Mainly, however, we
live on speculative investments, or on our prospects
only. But living on things in posse is
as good as living in the actual, so long as our
credit remains good. It is evident that for the
most part it is good, and that the universe
seldom protests our drafts. (Essay II § 7 ¶ 2)
In this sense we at every moment can continue to believe in an existing beyond. It is only in special cases that our confident rush forward gets rebuked. The beyond must, of course, always in our philosophy be itself of an experiential nature. If not a future experience of our own or a present one of our neighbor, it must be a thing in itself in Dr. Prince’s and Professor Strong’s sense of the term — that is, it must be an experience for itself whose relation to other things we translate into the action of molecules, ether-waves, or whatever else the physical symbols may be. This opens the chapter of the relations of radical empiricism to panspychism, into which I cannot enter now. (Essay II § 7 ¶ 3)
The beyond can in any case exist simultaneously
— for it can be experienced to have existed
simultaneously — with the experience
that practically postulates it by looking in its
direction, or by turning or changing in the
direction of which it is the goal. Pending that
actuality of union, in the virtuality of which
the truth,
even now, of the postulation consists,
the beyond and its knower are entities
split off from each other. The world is in so far
forth a pluralism of which the unity is not fully
experienced as yet. But, as fast as verifications
come, trains of experience, once separate, run
into one another; and that is why I said, earlier
in my article, that the unity of the world is on
the whole undergoing increase. The universe
continually grows in quantity by new experiences
that graft themselves upon the older
mass; but these very new experiences often
help the mass to a more consolidated form.
These are the main features of a philosophy
of pure experience. It has innumerable other
aspects and arouses innumerable questions,
but the points I have touched on seem enough
to make an entering wedge. In my own mind
such a philosophy harmonizes best with a radical
pluralism, with novelty and indeterminism,
moralism and theism, and with the humanism
lately sprung upon us by the Oxford and
the Chicago schools. I can not, however, be
sure that all these doctrines are its necessary
and indispensable allies. It presents so many
points of difference, both from the common
sense and from the idealism that have made
our philosophic language, that it is almost
difficult to state it as it is to think it out
clearly, and if it is ever to grow into a respectable
system, it will have to be built up by the
contributions of many co-operating minds. It
seems to me, as I said at the outset of this essay,
that many minds are, in point of fact, now
turning in a direction that points towards radical
empiricism. If they are carried farther by
my words, and if then they add their stronger
voices to my feebler one, the publication of
this essay will have been worth while. (Essay II § 7 ¶ 4)
Essay II § 7, n. 1: Our minds and these ejective realities would still have space (or pseudo-space, as I believe Professor Strong calls the medium of
interaction between things-in-themselves
) in common. These would
exist where, and begin to act where, we locate the molecules, etc.,
and where we perceive the sensible phenomena explained thereby. ↩
Essay II § 7, n. 2: [Cf. below, p. 188; A Pluralistic Universe, Lect. IV-VII.] ↩
Essay II § 7, n. 3: I have said something of this latter alliance in an article entitled Humanism and Truth, in Mind, October, 1904. [Reprinted in The Meaning of Truth, pp. 51-101. Cf. also Humanism and Truth Once More, below, pp. 244-265.] ↩