Chapter V: Ethics in Relation to Conduct.
§ 109.
The main points
in this chapter, to which I desire to direct attention, may be summarized as
follows:—(1) I first pointed out how the subject-matter with which it deals,
namely, ethical judgments on conduct, involves a question, utterly different in
kind from the two previously discussed, namely: (a) What is the nature
of the predicate peculiar to Ethics? and (b) What kinds of things
themselves possess this predicate? Practical Ethics asks, not What ought to
be?
but What ought we to do?
; it asks what actions are
duties, what actions are right, and what wrong: and
all these questions can only be answered by shewing the relation of the actions
in question, as causes or necessary conditions, to what is
good in itself. The enquiries of Practical Ethics thus fall entirely under the
third division of ethical questions—questions which ask, What is
good as a means?
which is equivalent to What is a means to good—what is
cause or necessary condition of things good in themselves?
(86—88). But (2) it asks this question, almost exclusively,
with regard to actions which it is possible for most men to perform, if only
they will them; and with regard to these, it does not ask merely, which
among them will have some good or bad result, but which, among all the
actions possible to volition at any moment, will produce the best total
result. To assert that an action is a duty, is to assert that it is such a
possible action, which will always, in certain known circumstances,
produce better results than any other. It follows that universal propositions of
which duty is predicate, so far from being self-evident, always require a proof,
which it is beyond our present means of knowledge ever to give (89—92). But (3) all that Ethics has attempted or can
attempt, is to shew that certain actions, possible by volition,
generally produce better or worse total results than any probable
alternative: and it must obviously be very difficult to shew this with regard to
the total results even in a comparatively near future; whereas that what has the
best results in such a near future, also has the best on the whole, is a point
requiring an investigation which it has not received. If it is true, and if,
accordingly, we give the name of duty
to actions which generally
produce better total results in the near future than any possible alternative,
it may be possible to prove that a few of the commonest rules of duty are true,
but only in certain conditions of society, which may be more or less
universally presented in history; and such a proof is only possible in
some cases without a correct judgment of what things are good or bad in
themselves—a judgment which has never yet been offered by ethical writers. With
regard to actions of which the general utility is thus proved, the
individual should always perform them; but in other cases, where rules
are commonly offered, he should rather judge of the probable results in his
particular case, guided by a correct conception of what things are intriniscally
good or bad (93—100). (4) In order that any action may
be shewn to be a duty, it must be shewn to fulfil the above conditions; but the
actions commonly called duties
do not fulfil them to any greater extent
than expedient
or interested
actions: by calling them
duties
we only mean that they have, in addition, certain
non-ethical predicates. Similarly by virtue
is mainly meant a permanent
disposition to perform duties
in this restricted sense: and accordingly a
virtue, if it is really a virtue, must be good as a means, in the sense
that it fulfils the above conditions; but it is not better as a means
than non-virtuous dispositions; it generally has no value in itself; and, where
it has, it is far from being the sole good or the best of goods. Accordingly
virtue
is not, as is commonly implied, an unique ethical
predicate (101—109). (§ 109 ¶ 1)