Chapter III: Hedonism.
§ 39.
I propose,
then, to begin by an examination of Mill’s Utilitarianism.
That is a book which contains an admirably clear and fair discussion of many
ethical principles and methods. Mill exposes not a few simple mistakes which are
very likely to be made by those who approach ethical problems without much
previous reflection. But what I am concerned with is the mistakes which Mill
himself appears to have made, and these only so far as they concern the
Hedonistic principle. Let me repeat what that principle is. It is, I said, that
pleasure is the only thing at which we ought to aim, the only thing that is good
as an end and for its own sake. And now let us turn to Mill and see whether he
accepts this description of the question at issue. Pleasure,
he
says at the outset, and freedom from pain, are the only things desirable as ends
(p.
10)*;
and again, at
the end of his argument, To think of an object as desirable (unless for
the sake of its consequences) and to think of it as pleasant are one and the
same thing
(p.
58). These statements, taken together, and apart from certain confusions
which are obvious in them, seem to imply the principle I have stated: and if I
succeed in shewing that Mill’s reasons for them do not prove them, it must at
least be admitted that I have not been fighting with shadows or demolishing a
man of straw. (§ 39 ¶ 1)
It will be observed that Mill adds absence of pain
to
pleasure
in his first statement, though not in his second. There is, in
this, a confusion, with which, however, we need not deal. I shall talk of
pleasure
alone, for the sake of conciseness; but all my arguments will
apply à fortiori to absence of pain
: it is
easy to make the necessary substitutions. (§ 39 ¶ 2)
Mill holds, then, that happiness is desirable, and the only thing
desirable, as an end; all other things being only desirable as means to
that end
(p.
52). Happiness he
has already defined as pleasure, and the absence of pain
(p.
10); he does not pretend that this is more than an
arbitrary verbal definition; and, as such, I
have not a word to say against it. His principle, then, is pleasure is the
only thing desirable,
if I may be allowed, when I say pleasure,
to
include in that word (so far as necessary) absence of pain. And now what are his
reasons for holding that principle to be true? He has already told us (p. 6)
that Questions of ultimate ends are not amenable to direct proof. Whatever
can be proved to be good, must be so by being shewn to be a means to something
admitted to be good without proof.
With this, I perfectly agree:
indeed the chief object of my first chapter was to shew
that this is so. Anything which is good as an end must be admitted to be good
without proof. We are agreed so far. Mill even uses the same examples which I
used in my second chapter. How,
he
says, is it possible to prove that health is good?
What proof is
it possible to give that pleasure is good?
Well, in Chapter
IV, in which he deals with the proof of his Utilitarian principle, Mill
repeats the above statement in these words: It has already,
he says,
been remarked, that questions of ultimate ends do not admit of proof, in the
ordinary acceptation of the term
(p.
52). Questions about ends,
he
goes on in this same passage, are, in other words, questions what things
are desirable.
I am quoting these repetitions, because they make it plain
what otherwise might have been doubted, that Mill is using the words
desirable
or desirable as an end
as absolutely and precisely
equivalent to the words good as an end.
We are, then, now to hear, what
reasons he advances for this doctrine that pleasure alone is good as an end.
(§ 39 ¶ 3)
§ 39, n. 1: My references are to the 13th edition, 1897. ↩
§ 39, n. 2: My italics. ↩
§ 40.
Questions
about ends,
he
says (pp. 52-3), are, in other words, questions about what things are
desirable. The utilitarian doctrine is, that happiness is desirable,
and the only thing desirable, as an end; all other things being only desirable
as means to that end. What ought to be required of this doctrine—what
conditions is it requisite that the doctrine should fulfil—to make good its
claim to be believed?
(§ 40 ¶ 1)
The only proof capable of being given that a thing is visible,
is that people actually see it. The only proof that a sound is audible, is that
people hear it; and so of the other sources of our experience. In like manner, I
apprehend, the sole evidence it is possible to produce that anything is
desirable, is that people do actually desire it. If the end which the
utilitarian doctrine proposes to itself were not, in theory and in practice,
acknowledged to be an end, nothing could ever convince any person that it was
so. No reason can be given why the general happiness is desirable, except that
each person, so far as he believes it to be attainable, desires his own
happiness. This, however, being the fact, we have not only all the proof which
the case admits of, but all which it is possible to require, that happiness is a
good: that each person’s happiness is a good to that person, and the general
happiness, therefore, a good to the aggregate of all persons. Happiness has made
out its title as one of the ends of conduct, and consequently one of
the criteria of morality.
(§ 40 ¶ 2)
There, that is enough. That is my first point. Mill has made as
naïve and artless a use of the naturalistic fallacy as anybody could desire.
Good,
he tells us, means desirable,
and you can only find out what
is desirable by seeking to find out what is actually desired. This is, of
course, only one step towards the proof of Hedonism; for it may be, as Mill goes
on to say, that other things beside pleasure are desired. Whether or not
pleasure is the only thing desired is, as
Mill himself admits (p. 58), a psychological question, to which we shall
presently proceed. The important step for Ethics is this one just taken, the
step which pretends to prove that good
means desired.
(§ 40 ¶ 3)
Well, the fallacy in this step is so obvious, that it is quite
wonderful how Mill failed to see it. The fact is that desirable
does not
mean able to be desired
as visible
means able to be seen.
The desirable means simply what ought to be desired or
deserves to be desired; just as the detestable means not what can be
but what ought to be detested and the damnable what deserves to be damned. Mill
has, then, smuggled in, under cover of the word desirable,
the very
notion about which he ought to be quite clear. Desirable
does indeed mean
what it is good to desire
; but when this is understood, it is no longer
plausible to say that our only test of that, is what is actually
desired. Is it merely a tautology when the Prayer Book talks of good
desires? Are not bad desires also possible? Nay, we find Mill himself
talking of a better and nobler object of desire
(p.
10), as if, after all, what is desired were not ipso
facto good, and good in proportion to the amount it is desired. Moreover,
if the desired is ipso facto the good; then the good
is ipso facto the motive of our actions, and there
can be no question of finding motives for doing it, as Mill is at such pains to
do. If Mill’s explanation of desirable
be true, then his
statement (p.
26) that the rule of action may be confounded with the motive of it
is untrue; for the motive of action will then be according to him ipso facto its rule; there can be no distinction between
the two, and therefore no confusion, and thus he has contradicted himself
flatly. These are specimens of the contradictions, which, as I have tried to
shew, must always follow from the use of the naturalistic fallacy; and I hope I
need now say no more about the matter. (§ 40 ¶ 4)
§ 41.
Well, then,
the first step by which Mill has attempted to establish his Hedonism is simply
fallacious. He has attempted to establish the identity of the good with the
desired, by confusing the proper sense of desirable,
in which it denotes
that which it is good to desire, with the sense which it would bear if it were
analogous to such words as visible.
If desirable
is to be
identical with good,
then it must bear one sense; and if it is to be
identical with desired,
then it must bear quite another sense. And yet to
Mill’s contention that the desired is necessarily good, it is quite essential
that these two senses of desirable
should be the same. If he holds they
are the same, then he has contradicted himself elsewhere; if he holds they are
not the same, then the first step in his proof of Hedonism is absolutely
worthless. (§ 41 ¶ 1)
But now we must deal with the second step. Having proved, as he
thinks, that the good means the desired, Mill recognises that, if he is further
to maintain that pleasure alone is good, he must prove that pleasure alone is
really desired. This doctrine that pleasure alone is the object of all our
desires
is the doctrine which Prof. Sidgwick has called Psychological
Hedonism: and it is a doctrine which most eminent psychologists are now agreed
in rejecting. But it is a necessary step in the proof of any such Naturalistic
Hedonism as Mill’s; and it is so commonly held, by people not expert either in
psychology or in philosophy, that I wish to treat it at some length. It will be
seen that Mill does not hold it in its bare form. He admits that other things
than pleasure are desired; and this admission is at once a contradiction of his
Hedonism. One of the shifts by which he seeks to evade this contradiction we
shall afterwards consider. But some may think that no such shifts are needed:
they may say of Mill, what
Callicles says of Polus in the Gorgias, that he has made the
fatal admission through a most unworthy fear of appearing paradoxical; that
they, on the other hand, will have the courage of their convictions, and will
not be ashamed to go to any lengths of paradox, in defence of what they hold to
be the truth. (§ 41 ¶ 2)
§ 42.
Well, then, we
are supposing it held that pleasure is the object of all desire, that it is the
universal end of all human activity. Now I suppose it will not be denied that
people are commonly said to desire other things: for instance, we usually talk
of desiring food and drink, of desiring money, approbation, fame. The question,
then, must be of what is meant by desire, and by the object of desire. There is
obviously asserted some sort of necessary or universal relation between
something which is called desire, and another thing which is called pleasure.
The question is of what sort this relation is; whether in conjunction with the
naturalistic fallacy above mentioned, it will justify Hedonism. Now I am not
prepared to deny that there is some universal relation between pleasure and
desire; but I hope to shew, that, if there is, it is of such sort as will rather
make against than for Hedonism. It is urged that pleasure is always the object
of desire, and I am ready to admit that pleasure is always, in part at least,
the cause of desire. But this distinction is very important. Both views
might be expressed in the same language; both might be said to hold that
whenever we desire, we always desire because of some pleasure: if I
asked my supposed Hedonist, Why do you desire that?
he might answer,
quite consistently with his contention, Because there is pleasure there,
and if he asked me the same question, I might answer, equally consistently with
my contention, Because there is pleasure here.
Only our two answers would
not mean the same thing. It is this use of the same language to denote quite
different facts, which I believe to be the chief cause why Psychological
Hedonism is so often held, just as it was also the cause of Mill’s naturalistic
fallacy. (§ 42 ¶ 1)
Let us try to analyze the psychological state which is called
desire.
That name is usually confined to a state of mind in which the
idea of some object or event, not yet existing, is present to us. Suppose, for
instance, I am desiring a glass of port wine. I have the idea of drinking such a
glass before my mind, although I am not yet drinking it. Well, how does pleasure
enter in to this relation? My theory is that it enters in, in this way. The
idea of the drinking causes a feeling of pleasure in my mind, which
helps to produce that state of incipient activity, which is called
desire.
It is, therefore, because of a pleasure, which I already
have—the pleasure excited by a mere idea—that I desire the wine, which I have
not. And I am ready to admit that a pleasure of this kind, an actual pleasure,
is always among the causes of every desire, and not only of every desire, but of
every mental activity, whether conscious or sub-conscious. I am ready to
admit this, I say: I cannot vouch that iti s the true psychological
doctrine; but, at all events, it is not primâ facie
quite absurd. And now, what is the other doctrine, the doctrine which I am
supposing held, and which is at all events essential to Mill’s argument? It is
this. That when I desire the wine, it is not the wine which I desire but the
pleasure which I expect to get from it. In other words, the doctrine is that the
idea of a pleasure not actual is always necessary to cause desire. It
is these two different theories which I suppose the Psychological Hedonists to
confuse: the confusion is, as Mr
Bradley puts it, between a pleasant thought
and the thought of a
pleasure.
It is in fact only where the latter, the thought of a
pleasure,
is present, that pleasure can be said to be the object of
desire, or the motive to action. On the other hand, when only a
pleasant thought is present, as, I admit, may always be the case, then
it is the object of the thought—that which we are thinking about—which is the
object of desire and the motive to action; and the pleasure, which that thought
excites, may, indeed, cause our desire or move us to action, but it is not our
end or object nor our motive. (§ 42 ¶ 2)
Well, I hope this distinction is sufficiently clear. Now let us see how it bears upon Ethical Hedonism. I assume it to be perfectly obvious that the idea of the object of desire is not always and only the idea of a pleasure. In the first place, plainly, we are not always conscious of expecting pleasure, when we desire a thing. We may be only conscious of the thing which we desire, and may be impelled to make for it at once, without any calculation as to whether it will bring us pleasure or pain. And, in the second place, even when we do expect pleasure, it can certainly be very rarely pleasure only which we desire. For instance, granted that, when I desire my glass of port wine, I have also an idea of the pleasure I expect from it, plainly that pleasure cannot be the only object of my desire; the port wine must be included in my object, else I might be led by my desire to take wormwood instead of wine. If the desire were directed solely towards the pleasure, it could not lead me to take the wine; if it is to take a definite direction, it is absolutely necessary that the idea of the object, from which the pleasure is expected, should also be present and should control my activity. The theory then that what is desired is always and only pleasure must break down: it is impossible to prove that pleasure alone is good, by that line of argument. But, if we substitute for this theory, that other, possibly true, theory, that pleasure is always the cause of desire, then all the plausibility of our ethical doctrine that pleasure alone is good straightaway disappears. For in this case, pleasure is not what I desire, it is not what I want: it is something which I already have, before I can want anything. And can any one feel inclined to maintain, that that which I already have, while I am still desiring something else, is always and alone the good? (§ 42 ¶ 3)
§ 42, n. 1: Ethical Studies, p. 282. ↩
§ 43.
But now let us
return to consider another of Mill’s arguments for his position that
happiness is the sole end of human action.
Mill admits, as I have said,
that pleasure is not the only thing we actually desire. The desire of
virtue,
he
says, is not as universal, but is as authentic a fact, as the desire of happiness.
And
again, Money is, in many cases, desired in and for itself.
These admissions
are, of course, in naked and glaring contradiction with his argument that
pleasure is the only thing desirable, because it is the only thing desired. How
then does Mill even attempt to avoid this contradiction?
His
chief argument seems to be that virtue,
money
and other such objects, when they
are thus desired in and for themselves, are desired only as a part of happiness.
Now what does this mean? Happiness, as we saw, has
been defined by Mill, as pleasure and the absence of pain.
Does Mill
mean to say that money,
these actual coins, which he admits to be desired
in and for themselves, are a part either of pleasure or of the absence of pain?
Will he maintain that those coins themselves are in my mind, and actually a part
of my pleasant feelings? If this is to be said, all words are useless: nothing
can possibly be distinguished from anything else; if these two things are not
distinct, what on earth is? We shall hear next that this table is really and
truly the same thing as this room; that a cab-horse is in fact indistinguishable
from St Paul’s Cathedral; that this book of Mill’s which I hold in
my hand, because it was his pleasure to produce it, is now and at this moment a
part of the happiness which he felt many years ago and which has so long ceased
to be. Pray consider a moment what this contemptible nonsense really means.
Money,
says Mill, is only desirable as a means to happiness.
Perhaps so, but what then? Why,
says Mill, money is undoubtedly
desired for its own sake.
Yes, go on,
say we. Well,
says Mill,
if money is desired for its own sake, it must be desirable as an
end-in-itself: I have said so myself.
Oh,
say we, but you have
also said just now that it was only desirable as a means.
I own I
did,
says Mill, but I will try to patch up matters, by saying that what
is only a means to an end, is the same thing as a part of that end. I daresay
the public won’t notice.
And the public haven’t noticed. Yet
this is certainly what Mill has done. He has broken down the distinction between
means and ends, upon the precise observance of which his Hedonism rests. And he
has been compelled to do this, because he failed to distinguish end
in
the sense of what is desirable, from end
in the sense of what is desired:
a distinction which, nevertheless, both the present argument and his whole book
presupposes. This is a consequence of the naturalistic fallacy. (§ 43 ¶ 1)
§ 44.
Mill, then, has nothing better to say for himself than this. His
two fundamental propositions are, in
his own words, that to think of an object as
desirable (unless for the sake of its consequences), and to think of it as
pleasant, are one and the same thing; and that desire anything except in
proportion as the idea of it is pleasant, is a physical and metaphysical
impossibility.
Both of these statements are, we have seen, merely
supported by fallacies. The first seems to rest on the naturalistic fallacy; the
second rests partly on this, partly on the fallacy of confusing ends and means,
and partly on the fallacy of confusing a pleasant thought with the thought of a
pleasure. His very language shews this. For that the idea of a thing is
pleasant, in his second clause, is obviously meant to be the same fact which he
denotes by thinking of it as pleasant,
in his first. (§ 44 ¶ 1)
Accordingly, Mill’s arguments for the proposition that pleasure is the sole good, and our refutation of those arguments, may be summed up as follows: (§ 44 ¶ 2)
First of all, he takes the desirable,
which he uses as a
synonym for the good,
to mean what can be desired. The
test, again, of what can be desired, is, according to him, what actually is
desired: if, therefore, he says, we can find some one thing which is always and
alone desired, that thing will necessarily be the only thing that is desirable,
the only thing that is good as an end. In this argument the naturalistic fallacy
is plainly involved. That fallacy, I explained, consists in the contention that
good means nothing but some simple or complex notion, that can be
defined in terms of natural qualities. In Mill’s case, good is thus supposed to
mean simply what is desired; and what is desired is something which can
thus be defined in natural terms. Mill tells us that we ought to desire
something (an ethical proposition), because we actually do desire it; but if his
contention that I ought to desire
means nothing but I do desire
were true, then he is only entitled to say, We do desire so and so, because
we do desire it
; and that is not an ethical proposition at all; it is a mere
tautology. The whole object of Mill’s book is to help us to discover what we
ought to do; but in fact, by attempting to define the meaning of this
ought,
he has completely debarred himself from ever fulfilling that
object: he has confined himself to telling us what we do do. (§ 44 ¶ 3)
Mill’s first argument then is that, because good means desired, therefore the desired is good; but having thus arrived at an ethical conclusion, by denying that any ethical conclusion is possible, he still needs another argument to make his conclusion a basis for Hedonism. He has to prove that we always do desire pleasure or freedom from pain, and that we never desire anything else whatever. This second doctrine, which Professor Sidgwick has called Psychological Hedonism, I accordingly discussed. I pointed out how obviously untrue it is that we never desire anything but pleasure; and how there is not a shadow of ground for saying even that, whenever we desire anything, we always desire pleasure as well as that thing. I attributed the obstinate belief in these untruths partly to a confusion between the cause of desire and the object of desire. It may, I said, be true that desire can never occur unless it be preceded by some actual pleasure; but even if this is true, it obviously gives no ground for saying that the object of desire is always some future pleasure. By the object of desire is meant that, of which the idea causes desire in us; it is some pleasure, which we anticipate, some pleasure which we have not got, which is the object of desire, whenever we do desire pleasure. And any actual pleasure, which may be excited by the idea of this anticipated pleasure, is obviously not the same pleasure as that anticipated pleasure, of which only the idea is actual. This actual pleasure is not what we want; what we want is always something which we have not got; and to say that pleasure always causes us to want is quite a different thing from saying that what we want is always pleasure. (§ 44 ¶ 4)
Finally, we saw, Mill admits all this. He insists that we do actually desire other things than pleasure, and yet he says we do really desire nothing else. He tries to explain away this contradiction, by confusing together two notions, which he has before carefully distinguished—the notions of means and of end. He now says that a means to an end is the same thing as a part of that end. To this last fallacy special attention should be given, as our ultimate decision with regard to Hedonism will largely turn upon it. (§ 44 ¶ 5)